বিষয়বস্তুতে চলুন

ব্যবহারকারী:প্রলয়স্রোত/অনুবাদের কুঁড়েঘর: সংশোধিত সংস্করণের মধ্যে পার্থক্য

উইকিপিডিয়া, মুক্ত বিশ্বকোষ থেকে
বিষয়বস্তু বিয়োগ হয়েছে বিষয়বস্তু যোগ হয়েছে
ট্যাগ: মোবাইল সম্পাদনা মোবাইল ওয়েব সম্পাদনা
ট্যাগ: মোবাইল সম্পাদনা মোবাইল ওয়েব সম্পাদনা
২২৪ নং লাইন: ২২৪ নং লাইন:
{{DEFAULTSORT:Homosexuality And Psychology}}
{{DEFAULTSORT:Homosexuality And Psychology}}
[[Category:Sexual orientation and psychology]]
[[Category:Sexual orientation and psychology]]

{{about|the concept in intelligent design|the concept in systems theory|Emergence}}
{{Intelligent Design}}

'''Irreducible complexity''' ('''IC''') is the argument that certain [[biological system]]s cannot [[evolution|evolve]] by successive small modifications to pre-existing functional systems through [[natural selection]]. Irreducible complexity is central to the [[creationism|creationist]] concept of [[intelligent design]], but it is rejected by the [[scientific community]],<ref name="dover_behe_ruling">"We therefore find that Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity has been refuted in peer-reviewed research papers and has been rejected by the scientific community at large." [[s:Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District/4:Whether ID Is Science#Page 79 of 139|Ruling, Judge John E. Jones III, ''Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District'']]</ref> which regards intelligent design as [[pseudoscience]].<ref>"True in this latest creationist variant, advocates of so-called intelligent design ... use more slick, pseudoscientific language. They talk about things like "irreducible complexity" {{cite book |author=Shulman, Seth |title=Undermining science: suppression and distortion in the Bush Administration |publisher=University of California Press |location=Berkeley |year=2006 |page=13 |isbn=0-520-24702-7}} "for most members of the mainstream scientific community, ID is not a scientific theory, but a creationist pseudoscience."<br/>{{cite journal|author=David Mu |title=Trojan Horse or Legitimate Science: Deconstructing the Debate over Intelligent Design |journal=Harvard Science Review |volume=19 |issue=1 |date=Fall 2005 |doi= |url=http://www.hcs.harvard.edu/~hsr/fall2005/mu.pdf |deadurl=yes |archiveurl=https://web.archive.org/web/20070724203349/http://www.hcs.harvard.edu/~hsr/fall2005/mu.pdf |archivedate=2007-07-24 |df= }}<br/>{{cite journal |author=Perakh M |title=Why Intelligent Design Isn't Intelligent — Review of: Unintelligent Design |journal=Cell Biol Educ. |volume=4 |issue=2 |pages=121–2 |date=Summer 2005 |doi=10.1187/cbe.05-02-0071 |pmc=1103713}}<br/>Mark D. Decker. College of Biological Sciences, General Biology Program, University of Minnesota [http://www.texscience.org/files/faqs.htm Frequently Asked Questions About the Texas Science Textbook Adoption Controversy] "The Discovery Institute and ID proponents have a number of goals that they hope to achieve using disingenuous and mendacious methods of marketing, publicity, and political persuasion. They do not practice real science because that takes too long, but mainly because this method requires that one have actual evidence and logical reasons for one's conclusions, and the ID proponents just don't have those. If they had such resources, they would use them, and not the disreputable methods they actually use."<br/>See also [[list of scientific societies explicitly rejecting intelligent design]]</ref> Irreducible complexity is one of two main arguments used by intelligent design proponents, the other being [[specified complexity]].<ref name="LiveScience- msnbc.com">{{cite web |url=http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/9452500/ns/technology_and_science-science/ |title=Why scientists dismiss 'intelligent design' - LiveScience |author=Ker Than|date=September 23, 2005 |publisher=[[msnbc.com]] |accessdate=2010-05-17}}</ref>

The theological [[teleological argument|argument from design]] was presented in [[creation science]] with assertions that evolution could not explain complex molecular mechanisms, and in 1993 [[Michael Behe]], a professor of biochemistry at Lehigh University, presented these arguments in a revised version of ''[[Of Pandas and People]]''.<ref name="bio design classrooms" /> In his 1996 book ''[[Darwin's Black Box]]'' he called this ''irreducible complexity'' and said it made evolution through natural selection of random mutations impossible.<ref>*{{cite book |last= Behe |first= Michael |title= Darwin's Black Box |publisher= Free Press |location= New York |year= 1996 |isbn= 978-0-684-82754-4}}</ref> This was based on the mistaken assumption that evolution relies on improvement of existing functions, ignoring how complex adaptations originate from changes in function, and disregarded published research.<ref name="bio design classrooms" /> [[evolutionary biology|Evolutionary biologists]] have published rebuttals showing how systems discussed by Behe can evolve,<ref name="thornton2006"/><ref name="Redundant Complexity"/> and examples documented through [[comparative genomics]] show that complex molecular systems are formed by the addition of components as revealed by different temporal origins of their proteins.<ref>http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/v481/n7381/full/nature10724.html</ref><ref>http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2148/10/341</ref>

In the 2005 ''[[Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District]]'' trial, Behe gave testimony on the subject of irreducible complexity. The court found that "Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity has been refuted in peer-reviewed research papers and has been rejected by the scientific community at large."<ref name="dover_behe_ruling"/>

==Definitions==
[[Michael Behe]] defined irreducible complexity in natural selection in his book ''[[Darwin's Black Box]]'':
<blockquote>... a single system which is composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, and where the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning.<ref>''Darwin's Black Box'' page 39 in the 2006 edition</ref></blockquote>

A second definition given by Behe (his "evolutionary definition") is as follows:
<blockquote>An irreducibly complex evolutionary pathway is one that contains one or more unselected steps (that is, one or more necessary-but-unselected mutations). The degree of irreducible complexity is the number of unselected steps in the pathway.<ref>''In Defense of the Irreducibility of the Blood Clotting Cascade: Response to Russell Doolittle, Ken Miller and Keith Robison'', July 31, 2000, [http://www.discovery.org/a/442 Discovery Institute article]</ref></blockquote>

Intelligent design advocate [[William A. Dembski]] gives this definition:
<blockquote>A system performing a given basic function is irreducibly complex if it includes a set of well-matched, mutually interacting, nonarbitrarily individuated parts such that each part in the set is indispensable to maintaining the system's basic, and therefore original, function. The set of these indispensable parts is known as the irreducible core of the system.<ref>''No Free Lunch: Why Specified Complexity Cannot Be Purchased without Intelligence.'' by William Dembski pp. 285</ref></blockquote>

==History==

===Forerunners===
The argument from irreducible complexity is a descendant of the [[teleological argument]] for God (the argument from design or from complexity). This states that because certain things in nature appear very complicated, they must have been designed. [[William Paley]] famously argued, in his 1802 [[watchmaker analogy]], that complexity in nature implies a God for the same reason that the existence of a watch implies the existence of a watchmaker.<ref name="paley"/> This argument has a long history, and one can trace it back at least as far as [[Cicero]]'s ''[[De Natura Deorum]]'' ii.34,<ref>''On the Nature of the Gods'', translated by Francis Brooks, London: Methuen, 1896.</ref><ref>See [[Henry Hallam]] [https://books.google.com/books?id=FpDzTASTVwsC&pg=PA385 ''Introduction to the Literature of Europe in the Fifteenth, Sixteenth, and Seventeenth Centuries'' Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1854] volume 2 page 385 part iii chapter iii section i paragraph 26 footnote ''u''</ref> written in 45 BC.

====Up to the 18th century====

[[Galen]] (1st and 2nd centuries AD) wrote about the large number of parts of the body and their relationships, which observation was cited as evidence for creation.<ref>''De Formatione Foetus''=''The Construction of the Embryo'', chapter 11 in ''Galen: Selected Works'', translated by P. N. Singer, ''The World's Classics'', Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1997 {{ISBN|978-0-19-282450-9}}. One 18th-century reference to Galen is [http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/dnr.htm#A13 [[David Hume]] ''[[Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion]]'', 1779, Part 12], &sect; 3, page 215. Also see Galen's ''De Usu Partium''=''On the Usefulness of the Parts of the Body'', translated and edited by Margaret Tallmadge May, Ithaca, New York, Cornell University Press, 1968, especially book XVII. For a relevant discussion of Galen and other ancients see pages 121-122, {{cite book |author= Goodman, Lenn Evan |title= Creation and evolution |location= Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon and New York |publisher= Routledge |year= 2010 |isbn= 978-0-415-91380-5}}</ref> The idea that the interdependence between parts would have implications for the origins of living things was raised by writers starting with [[Pierre Gassendi]] in the mid-17th century<ref>''De Generatione Animalium'', chapter III. Partial translation in: Howard B. Adelmann, ''Marcello Malpighi and the Evolution of Embryology'' Ithaca, New York, Cornell University Press, 1966, volume 2, pages 811-812.</ref> and by [[John Wilkins]] (1614-1672), who wrote (citing Galen), "Now to imagine, that all these things, according to their several kinds, could be brought into this regular frame and order, to which such an infinite number of Intentions are required, without the contrivance of some wise Agent, must needs be irrational in the highest degree."<ref>John Wilkins,''Of the Principles and Duties of Natural Religion'', London, 1675, book I, chapter 6, page 82.</ref> In the late 17th-century, [[Thomas Burnet]] referred to "a multitude of pieces aptly joyn'd" to argue against the [[eternity]] of life.<ref>[http://www.sacred-texts.com/earth/ste/ste07.htm ''The Sacred Theory of the Earth''], 2nd edition, London: Walter Kettilby, 1691. Book I Chapter IV page 43</ref> In the early 18th century, [[Nicolas Malebranche]]<ref>{{cite book|author= Nicolas Malebranche|title= De la recherche de la verité: où l'on traite de la nature de l'esprit de l'homme, & de l'usage qu'il en doit faire pour éviter l'erreur dans les sciences|edition= 6ième|location= Paris|publisher= Chez Michel David|year= 1712|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=Gi0_AAAAcAAJ&pg=RA1-PA57&vq=%22d%C3%A9pendent%20mutuellement%22}} Livre 6ième, 2ième partie, chapître 4; English translation: {{cite book|author= Nicholas Malebranche|title= The Search After Truth: With Elucidations of The Search After Truth|editor1= Thomas M. Lennon |editor2= Paul J. Olscamp |location= Cambridge|publisher= Cambridge University Press|year= 1997|isbn= 0-521-58004-8|url= https://books.google.com/books?id=ybYLfAw_084C&pg=PA465&vq=%22mutually%20depend%22}} Second paragraph from the end of the chapter, on page 465.</ref> wrote "An organized body contains an infinity of parts that mutually depend upon one another in relation to particular ends, all of which must be actually formed in order to work as a whole", arguing in favor of [[preformation]], rather than [[epigenesis (biology)|epigenesis]], of the individual;<ref>Pages 202-204 of {{cite book|author= [[Andrew Pyle (philosopher)|Andrew Pyle]] |chapter= Malebranche on Animal Generation: Preexistence and the Microscope |editor= Smith JH |title= The problem of animal generation in early modern philosophy |publisher= Cambridge University Press |location= Cambridge, UK |year= 2006 |pages= 194–214 |isbn= 0-521-84077-5 |url= https://books.google.com/?id=EyMWhGH4JgIC&pg=PA204&dq=%22irreducible+complexity%22+intitle:problem+intitle:of+intitle:generation+inauthor:smith#v=onepage&q=%22irreducible%20complexity%22%20intitle%3Aproblem%20intitle%3Aof%20intitle%3Ageneration%20inauthor%3Asmith&f=false}}</ref> and a similar argument about the origins of the individual was made by other 18th-century students of natural history.<ref>[http://talkreason.org/articles/chickegg.cfm The Chicken or the Egg]</ref> In his 1790 book, ''[[The Critique of Judgment#Teleology|The Critique of Judgment]]'', [[Immanuel Kant|Kant]] is said by Guyer to argue that "we cannot conceive how a whole that comes into being only gradually from its parts can nevertheless be the cause of the properties of those parts".<ref>This is Guyer's exposition on page 22 of {{cite book|editor= Paul Guyer|title= The Cambridge Companion to Kant|author= Paul Guyer|authorlink= Paul Guyer|chapter= Introduction|pages= 1–25|location= Cambridge|publisher= Cambridge University Press|year= 1992|isbn= 978-0-521-36768-4 |url= https://books.google.com/?id=pYE5rVzrPNgC&pg=PA22&dq=%22gradually+from+its+parts%22+intitle:cambridge+intitle:companion+intitle:to+intitle:kant+inauthor:guyer#v=onepage&q=%22gradually%20from%20its%20parts%22%20intitle%3Acambridge%20intitle%3Acompanion%20intitle%3Ato%20intitle%3Akant%20inauthor%3Aguyer&f=false}} Guyer adds this parenthetical comment: "(here is where the theory of natural selection removes the difficulty)". See Kant's discussion in section IX of the "First Introduction" to the ''Critique of Judgment'' and in §§61, 64 (where he uses the expression ''wechselsweise abhängt''="reciprocally dependent"), and §66 of "Part Two, First Division". For example, {{cite book |url= https://books.google.com/?id=JEXHIcDbBDcC&pg=PA243&dq=%22reciprocally+dependent%22+intitle:critique+intitle:judgment+inauthor:kant#v=onepage&q=%22reciprocally%20dependent%22%20intitle%3Acritique%20intitle%3Ajudgment%20inauthor%3Akant&f=false |title= Critique of the power of judgment |author= Immanuel Kant |editor1= Paul Guyer |editor2= Eric Matthews |location= Cambridge |publisher= Cambridge University Press |year= 2000 |isbn= 0-521-34447-6 |pages= 243–244 |chapter= §64 }} German original {{cite book |title= Kritik der Urtheilskraft |url= https://books.google.com/?id=6O1Nayo3wWgC&pg=PA371&dq=akademie+%22wechselsweise+abhängt%22+inauthor:kant#v=onepage&q&f=false |volume= 5 |page= 371 |location= Berlin |publisher= Georg Reimer |edition= Königlich Preußischen Akademie der Wißenschaften |series= Kants gesammelte Schriften |year= 1913 |isbn= 978-3-11-001438-9 }}</ref>

====19th century====
Chapter XV of Paley's ''Natural Theology'' discusses at length what he called "relations" of parts of living things as an indication of their design.<ref name="paley">[http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?itemID=A142&viewtype=text&pageseq=1 William Paley:''Natural Theology; or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity. Collected from the Appearances of Nature'' 12th edition, 1809]</ref>

[[Georges Cuvier]] applied his principle of the ''correlation of parts'' to describe an animal from fragmentary remains. For Cuvier, this related to another principle of his, the ''conditions of existence'', which excluded the possibility of [[transmutation of species]].<ref>See especially chapters VI and VII of {{cite book|author= William Coleman |title= Georges Cuvier, Zoologist: A Study in the History of Evolution Theory |location= Cambridge, Massachusetts |publisher= Harvard University Press |year= 1964}} See also the discussion of these principles in the Wikipedia article on [[Georges Cuvier|Cuvier]].</ref>

While he did not originate the term, [[Charles Darwin]] identified the argument as a possible way to falsify a prediction of the theory of evolution at the outset. In ''[[The Origin of Species]]'' (1859), he wrote, "If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed, which could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modifications, my theory would absolutely break down. But I can find out no such case."<ref>[[Charles Darwin|Darwin, Charles]] (1859). ''[[The Origin of Species|On the Origin of Species]]''. London: John Murray. [http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?itemID=F373&viewtype=side&pageseq=207 page 189, Chapter VI]</ref> Darwin's theory of evolution challenges the teleological argument by postulating an alternative explanation to that of an intelligent designer—namely, evolution by natural selection. By showing how simple unintelligent forces can ratchet up designs of extraordinary complexity without invoking outside design, Darwin showed that an intelligent designer was not the necessary conclusion to draw from complexity in nature. The argument from irreducible complexity attempts to demonstrate that certain biological features cannot be purely the product of Darwinian evolution.<ref>See for example, {{cite book|author= Alan R. Rogers|authorlink=Alan R. Rogers|title= The Evidence for Evolution|location= Chicago|publisher= University of Chicago Press|year= 2011|isbn= 978-0-226-72382-2}} in pages 37–38, 48–49 citing Joseph John Murphy accepting natural selection within limits, excepting "the eye" with its multiple parts. {{cite news|author= Joseph John Murphy|title= Presidential Address to the Belfast Natural History and Philosophical Society|journal= Northern Whig|location= Belfast|date= November 19, 1866|url= http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?viewtype=image&itemID=CUL-DAR226.1.118-119&pageseq=1}} and in page 48 citing {{cite book|author=C. Pritchard|authorlink=Charles Pritchard|title=The Continuity of the Schemes of Nature and Revelation: A Sermon Preached, by request, on the occasion of the meeting of the British Association at Nottingham. With remarks on some relations of modern knowledge to theology|chapter=Appendix Note A On the Origin of Species by Natural Selection|pages=31-37|location=London|publisher=Bell and Daldy|url=https://archive.org/details/continuityofsche00prit}}, especially page 33</ref>

In the late 19th century, in a dispute between supporters of the adequacy of [[natural selection]] and those who held for [[inheritance of acquired characteristics]], one of the arguments made repeatedly by [[Herbert Spencer]], and followed by others, depended on what Spencer referred to as ''co-adaptation'' of ''co-operative'' parts, as in: <blockquote>"We come now to Professor [[August Weismann|Weismann]]'s endeavour to disprove my second thesis — that it is impossible to explain by natural selection alone the co-adaptation of co-operative parts. It is thirty years since this was set forth in "The Principles of Biology." In §166, I instanced the enormous horns of the extinct [[Irish elk]], and contended that in this and in kindred cases, where for the efficient use of some one enlarged part many other parts have to be simultaneously enlarged, it is out of the question to suppose that they can have all spontaneously varied in the required proportions."<ref>Page 594 in: {{cite journal|author= Herbert Spencer|title= Weismannism Once More|journal= [[The Contemporary Review]]|date= October 1894|volume= 66 |pages= 592–608}} Another essay of Spencer's treating this concept is: {{cite journal|author= Herbert Spencer |title= The Inadequacy of "Natural Selection" |journal= The Contemporary Review |volume= 63 |year= 1893 |pages= 153–166}} (Part I: February) and pages 439-456 (Part II: March). These essays were reprinted in {{cite book|author= Herbert Spencer|title= The Works of Herbert Spencer|year= 1891|place= London|publisher= Williams and Norgate|volume= 17}} (also Osnabrück: Otto Zeller, 1967). See also part III, Chapter XII, §166, pages 449-457 in: {{cite book |author= Herbert Spencer |title= Principles of Biology |year= 1864 |place= London |publisher= Williams and Norgate|volume= I}} And: {{cite journal|journal= [[The Nineteenth Century (periodical)|The Nineteenth Century]] |author= Herbert Spencer|title= The Factors of Organic Evolution |volume= 19 |year= 1886 |pages= 570–589}} (Part I: April) and pages 749-770 (Part II: May). "Factors" was reprinted in pages 389-466 of {{cite book|author= Herbert Spencer|title= The Works of Herbert Spencer|volume= 13|location= London|publisher= Williams and Norgate|year= 1891}} (also Osnabrück: Otto Zeller, 1967)= volume 1 of ''Essays: Scientific, Political, and Speculative''.</ref><ref>One example of a response was in Section III(γ) pages 32-42 of {{cite book|author= August Weismann |chapter= The Selection theory |pages= 19–65 |title= Darwin and Modern Science: Essays in Commemoration of the Centenary of the Birth of Charles Darwin and of the Fiftieth Anniversary of the Publication of The Origin of Species|editor= [[Albert Charles Seward]]|location= Cambridge |publisher= Cambridge University Press |year= 1909}} See also Chapter VII, §12(1), pages 237-238 in: {{cite book|author= [[J. Arthur Thomson]]|title= Heredity|place= London|publisher= John Murray|year= 1908}} Both of these referred to what has become known as the [[Baldwin effect]]. An analysis of both sides of the issue is: {{cite book |author= [[George John Romanes]] |title= Darwin and After Darwin: Post-Darwinian Questions, Heredity, Utility |volume= II |chapter= III: Characters as Hereditary and Acquired (continued) |pages= 60–102 |place= London |publisher= Longman, Green |year= 1895}}</ref></blockquote> Darwin responded to Spencer's objections in chapter XXV of ''[[The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication]]'' (1868).<ref>{{cite book|title= The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication|author= Charles Darwin|year= 1868|location= London|publisher= John Murray|chapter= XXV. Laws of Variation ''continued'' - Correlated Variability|volume= 2|pages= 321–338|url= http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?keywords=co%20ordinated&pageseq=236&itemID=F877.2&viewtype=text}} especially page 333 and following.</ref> The history of this concept in the dispute has been characterized: "An older and more religious tradition of idealist thinkers were committed to the explanation of complex adaptive contrivances by intelligent design. ... Another line of thinkers, unified by the recurrent publications of Herbert Spencer, also saw [[co-adaptation]] as a composed, irreducible whole, but sought to explain it by the inheritance of acquired characteristics."<ref>Pages 67-68 in: {{cite journal|author= [[Mark Ridley (zoologist)|Mark Ridley]]|title= Coadapatation and the Inadequacy of Natural Selection|journal= British Journal for the History of Science |volume= 15|issue= 1 |date= March 1982 |pages= 45–68 |doi= 10.1017/S0007087400018938}}</ref>

[[St. George Jackson Mivart]] raised the objection to natural selection that "Complex and simultaneous co-ordinations … until so far developed as to effect the requisite junctions, are useless"<ref>{{cite book|title= On the Genesis of Species|author= [[St. George Jackson Mivart]]|location= London|publisher= Macmillan|year= 1871|page= 52}}</ref> which "amounts to the concept of "irreducible complexity" as defined by … Michael Behe".<ref>{{cite book|author= Asher, Robert J.|title= Evolution and belief: confessions of a religious paleontologist|location= Cambridge & New York|publisher= Cambridge University Press|year= 2012|isbn= 9780521193832|page= 214}} See also [http://www.veritas-ucsb.org/library/origins/quotes/irreducible.html Irreducible Complexity] and the references cited there.</ref>

====20th century====
[[Hermann Joseph Muller|Hermann Muller]], in the early 20th century, discussed a concept similar to irreducible complexity. However, far from seeing this as a problem for evolution, he described the "interlocking" of biological features as a consequence to be expected of evolution, which would lead to irreversibility of some evolutionary changes.<ref name="Muller_1918">{{cite journal |author= Muller HJ |title= Genetic variability, twin hybrids and constant hybrids, in a case of balanced lethal factors |journal= Genetics |volume= 3 |issue= 5 |pages= 422–99 |year= 1918 |url= http://www.genetics.org/cgi/reprint/3/5/422|pmid=17245914 |pmc= 1200446}}, especially pages 463–4.</ref> He wrote, "Being thus finally woven, as it were, into the most intimate fabric of the organism, the once novel character can no longer be withdrawn with impunity, and may have become vitally necessary."<ref>{{cite journal |author= Muller HJ |title= Reversibility in evolution considered from the standpoint of genetics |journal= Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society |volume= 4 |issue= 3 |pages= 261–80, quotation from 272 |year= 1939}}</ref>

In 1974 the [[young Earth creationism|young Earth creationist]] [[Henry M. Morris]] introduced a similar concept in his book ''Scientific Creationism'', in which he wrote; "This issue can actually be attacked quantitatively, using simple principles of mathematical probability. The problem is simply whether a complex system, in which many components function unitedly together, and in which each component is uniquely necessary to the efficient functioning of the whole, could ever arise by random processes."<ref>{{cite book |author= [[Henry M. Morris|Morris, Henry]] |title= Scientific creationism |publisher= Creation-Life Publishers |location= San Diego, Calif |year= 1974 |page= 59 |isbn= 0-89051-003-2 |edition= 2nd}}</ref>

In 1975 [[Thomas H. Frazzetta]] published a book-length study of a concept similar to irreducible complexity, explained by gradual, step-wise, non-teleological evolution. Frazzetta wrote: <blockquote>"A complex adaptation is one constructed of ''several'' components that must blend together operationally to make the adaptation "work". It is analogous to a machine whose performance depends upon careful cooperation among its parts. In the case of the machine, no single part can greatly be altered without changing the performance of the entire machine."</blockquote> The machine that he chose as an analog is the [[Peaucellier–Lipkin linkage]], and one biological system given extended description was the jaw apparatus of a python. The conclusion of this investigation, rather than that evolution of a complex adaptation was impossible, "awed by the adaptations of living things, to be stunned by their complexity and suitability", was "to accept the inescapable but not humiliating fact that much of mankind can be seen in a tree or a lizard."<ref>T. H. Frazzetta, ''Complex Adaptations in Evolving Populations'', Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates, 1975. {{ISBN|0-87893-194-5}}. Referencing pages 3, 4-7, 7-20, and xi, respectively.</ref>

In 1981, Ariel Roth, in defense of the [[creation science|creation-science]] position in the trial ''[[McLean v. Arkansas]]'', said of "complex integrated structures": "This system would not be functional until all the parts were there ... How did these parts survive during evolution ...?"<ref>{{cite book |author1= Keough, Mark J. |author2= Geisler, Norman L. |title= The Creator in the courtroom "Scopes II": the 1981 Arkansas creation-evolution trial |publisher= Mott Media |location= Milford, Mich |year= 1982 |page= 146 |isbn= 0-88062-020-X |url= http://www.antievolution.org/projects/mclean/new_site/docs/geislerbook.htm#Chapter%20Seven}}</ref>

In 1985 [[Graham Cairns-Smith|Cairns-Smith]] wrote of "interlocking": "How can a complex collaboration between components evolve in small steps?" and used the analogy of the scaffolding called [[centring|centering]] - used to [[arch#Construction|build an arch]] then removed afterwards: "Surely there was 'scaffolding'. Before the multitudinous components of present biochemistry could come to lean together ''they had to lean on something else.''"<ref>{{cite book |author= Cairns-Smith, A. G. |title= Seven clues to the origin of life: a scientific detective story |publisher= Cambridge University Press |location= Cambridge, UK |year= 1985 |pages= 39, 58–64 |isbn= 0-521-27522-9}}</ref><ref>McShea, Daniel W. and Wim Hordijk. "[http://link.springer.com/article/10.1007%2Fs11692-013-9227-6 Complexity by Subtraction]." ''Evolutionary Biology'' (April 2013). [http://www.worldwidewanderings.net/Professional/Publications/complsub.pdf PDF].</ref> However, neither Muller or Cairns-Smith claimed their ideas as evidence of something supernatural.<ref>{{cite journal |url= http://www.skeptic.com/the_magazine/ |title= Bacteria Flagella Look Like Man-made Machines |author= [[Mark Perakh]] |publisher= ''[[Skeptic (U.S. magazine)]]'' |year= 2008 |volume= 14 |issue= 3 |accessdate= 2008-12-06}}</ref>

An essay in support of [[creationism]] published in 1994 referred to bacterial [[flagella]] as showing "multiple, integrated components", where "nothing about them works unless every one of their complexly fashioned and integrated components are in place". The author asked the reader to "imagine the effects of natural selection on those organisms that fortuitously evolved the flagella ... without the concommitant {{sic}} control mechanisms".<ref>{{cite journal |author= Lumsden RD |title= Not So Blind A Watchmaker |journal= Creation Research Society Quarterly |volume= 31 |issue= 1 |pages= 13–22, quotations from 13, 20 |date= June 1994}}</ref><ref name="bio design classrooms">{{cite journal |vauthors= Scott EC, Matzke NJ |title= Biological design in science classrooms |journal= Proc Natl Acad Sci USA |volume= 104 |issue= suppl_1|pages= 8669–76, See page 8672 |date= May 2007 |pmid= 17494747 |pmc= 1876445 |doi= 10.1073/pnas.0701505104 |bibcode= 2007PNAS..104.8669S}}</ref>

An early concept of irreducibly complex systems comes from [[Ludwig von Bertalanffy]] (1901-1972), an Austrian biologist.<ref>Ludwig von Bertalanffy (1952). ''Problems of Life: An Evaluation of Modern Biological and Scientific Thought, pg 148'' {{ISBN|1-131-79242-4}}</ref> He believed that complex systems must be examined as complete, [[irreducibility|irreducible]] systems in order to fully understand how they work. He extended his work on biological complexity into a general theory of systems in a book titled ''[[systems theory|General Systems Theory]]''.

After [[James Watson]] and [[Francis Crick]] published the structure of [[DNA]] in the early 1950s, General Systems Theory lost many of its adherents in the physical and biological sciences.<ref>
{{cite book
|author= Monod, Jacques
|title= Chance and necessity: an essay on the natural philosophy of modern biology
|publisher= Vintage Books |location= New York
|year= 1972 |isbn= 0-394-71825-9
}}
</ref>
However, Systems theory remained popular in the social sciences long after its demise in the physical and biological sciences.

===Origins===
[[File:Darwinsblackbox.jpg|thumb|right|160px|[[Michael Behe]]'s controversial book ''[[Darwin's Black Box]]'' popularized the concept of irreducible complexity.]]
[[Michael Behe]] developed his ideas on the concept around 1992, in the early days of the '[[wedge strategy|wedge movement]]', and first presented his ideas about "irreducible complexity" in June 1993 when the "Johnson-Behe cadre of scholars" met at Pajaro Dunes in California.<ref name=bfwedge>[[Barbara Forrest]], [http://www.talkreason.org/articles/Wedge.cfm#I The Wedge at Work] {{webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140905230611/http://www.talkreason.org/articles/Wedge.cfm |date=2014-09-05 }}. Talk Reason.<br/>{{cite book |author=Forrest B |editor=Pennock RT |chapter=1: The Wedge at Work: How Intelligent Design Creationism is Wedging its way into the Cultural and Academic Mainstream |title=Intelligent design creationism and its critics: philosophical, theological, and scientific perspectives |publisher=MIT Press |location=Cambridge, Mass |year=2001 |pages=5–54 |isbn=0-262-66124-1}}</ref> He set out his ideas in the second edition of ''[[Of Pandas and People]]'' published in 1993, extensively revising Chapter 6 ''Biochemical Similarities'' with new sections on the complex mechanism of blood clotting and on the origin of proteins.<ref>[http://ncseweb.org/creationism/analysis/new-pandas-has-creationist-scholarship-improved The New Pandas: Has Creationist Scholarship Improved?] Comments on 1993 Revisions by Frank J. Sonleitner (1994)<br/>[http://ncseweb.org/creationism/analysis/critique-pandas-people Introduction: Of Pandas and People, the foundational work of the 'Intelligent Design' movement] by Nick Matzke 2004,<br/>[http://ncseweb.org/rncse/26/1-2/design-trial Design on Trial in Dover, Pennsylvania] by Nicholas J Matzke, NCSE Public Information Project Specialist</ref>

He first used the term "irreducible complexity" in his 1996 book ''[[Darwin's Black Box]]'', to refer to certain complex biochemical [[cell (biology)|cellular]] systems. He posits that evolutionary mechanisms cannot explain the development of such "irreducibly complex" systems. Notably, Behe credits philosopher [[William Paley]] for the original concept (alone among the predecessors) and suggests that his application of the concept to biological systems is entirely original.

Intelligent design advocates argue that irreducibly complex systems must have been deliberately engineered by some form of [[intelligent designer|intelligence]].

In 2001, [[Michael Behe]] wrote: "[T]here is an asymmetry between my current definition of irreducible complexity and the task facing natural selection. I hope to repair this defect in future work." Behe specifically explained that the "current definition puts the focus on removing a part from an already functioning system", but the "difficult task facing Darwinian evolution, however, would not be to remove parts from sophisticated pre-existing systems; it would be to bring together components to make a new system in the first place".<ref>{{cite journal |author=Behe MJ |title=Reply to My Critics: A Response to Reviews of Darwin's Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution |journal=Biology and Philosophy |volume=16 |issue=5 |pages=685–709 |date=November 2001 |url=http://friends-of-wisdom.com/readings/Behe2001.pdf |doi=10.1023/A:1012268700496 }}</ref> In the 2005 ''[[Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District]]'' trial, Behe testified under oath that he "did not judge [the asymmetry] serious enough to [have revised the book] yet."<ref>[http://www.talkorigins.org/faqs/dover/day12am2.html Behe's testimony in ''Kitzmiller v. Dover'']</ref>

Behe additionally testified that the presence of irreducible complexity in organisms would not rule out the involvement of evolutionary mechanisms in the development of organic life. He further testified that he knew of no earlier "peer reviewed articles in scientific journals discussing the intelligent design of the blood clotting cascade," but that there were "probably a large number of peer reviewed articles in science journals that demonstrate that the blood clotting system is indeed a purposeful arrangement of parts of great complexity and sophistication."<ref>Behe, Michael 2005 [[Wikisource:Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District/4:Whether ID Is Science#Page 88 of 139|Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District 4: whether ID is science (p. 88)]]</ref> (The judge ruled that "intelligent design is not science and is essentially religious in nature".)<ref>[[s:Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District/6:Curriculum, Conclusion#H. Conclusion|Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District 6: Conclusion, section H]]</ref>

According to the theory of evolution, genetic variations occur without specific design or intent. The environment "selects" the variants that have the highest fitness, which are then passed on to the next generation of organisms. Change occurs by the gradual operation of natural forces over time, perhaps slowly, perhaps more quickly (see [[punctuated equilibrium]]). This process is able to [[adaptation|adapt]] complex structures from simpler beginnings, or convert complex structures from one function to another (see [[spandrel (biology)|spandrel]]). Most intelligent design advocates accept that evolution occurs through mutation and natural selection at the "[[microevolution|micro level]]", such as changing the relative frequency of various beak lengths in finches, but assert that it cannot account for irreducible complexity, because none of the parts of an irreducible system would be functional or advantageous until the entire system is in place.

===The mousetrap example===
[[File:Mausefalle 300px.jpg|thumb|200px|[[Michael Behe]] believes that many aspects of life show evidence of design, using the [[mousetrap]] in an analogy disputed by others.<ref name=trap>[http://udel.edu/~mcdonald/mousetrap.html A reducibly complex mousetrap] (graphics-intensive, requires [[JavaScript]])</ref>]]

Behe uses the mousetrap as an illustrative example of this concept. A mousetrap consists of five interacting pieces: the base, the catch, the spring, the hammer, and the hold-down bar. All of these must be in place for the mousetrap to work, as the removal of any one piece destroys the function of the mousetrap. Likewise, he asserts that biological systems require multiple parts working together in order to function. Intelligent design advocates claim that natural selection could not create from scratch those systems for which science is currently unable to find a viable evolutionary pathway of successive, slight modifications, because the selectable function is only present when all parts are assembled.

In his 2008 book ''[[Only A Theory]]'', biologist [[Kenneth R. Miller]] challenges Behe's claim that the mousetrap is irreducibly complex.<ref name=Only /> Miller observes that various subsets of the five components can be devised to form cooperative units, ones that have different functions from the mousetrap and so, in biological terms, could form functional [[spandrel (biology)|spandrels]] before being adapted to the new function of catching mice. In an example taken from his high school experience, Miller recalls that one of his classmates<blockquote>...struck upon the brilliant idea of using an old, broken mousetrap as a spitball catapult, and it worked brilliantly.... It had worked perfectly as something other than a mousetrap.... my rowdy friend had pulled a couple of parts --probably the hold-down bar and catch-- off the trap to make it easier to conceal and more effective as a catapult... [leaving] the base, the spring, and the hammer. Not much of a mousetrap, but a helluva spitball launcher.... I realized why [Behe's] mousetrap analogy had bothered me. It was wrong. The mousetrap is not irreducibly complex after all.<ref name=Only>{{cite book |title= Only A Theory |first= Kenneth R. |last= Miller |location= New York |year= 2008 |publisher= Viking Penguin |pages= 54–55 |isbn= 978-0-670-01883-3}}</ref></blockquote>

Other systems identified by Miller that include mousetrap components include the following:<ref name= Only/>
*use the spitball launcher as a tie clip (same three-part system with different function)
*remove the spring from the spitball launcher/tie clip to create a two-part key chain (base + hammer)
*glue the spitball launcher/tie clip to a sheet of wood to create a clipboard (launcher + glue + wood)
*remove the hold-down bar for use as a toothpick (single element system)

The point of the reduction is that - in biology - most or all of the components were already at hand, by the time it became necessary to build a mousetrap. As such, it required far fewer steps to develop a mousetrap than to design all the components from scratch.

Thus, the development of the mousetrap, said to consist of five different parts which had no function on their own, has been reduced to one step: the assembly from parts that are already present, performing other functions.

The Intelligent Design argument focuses on the functionality to catch mice. It skips over the case that many, if not all, parts are already available in their own right, at the time that the need for a mousetrap arises.

===Consequences of irreducible complexity===
Supporters of intelligent design argue that anything less than the complete form of such a system or organ would not work at all, or would in fact be a ''detriment'' to the organism, and would therefore never survive the process of natural selection. Although they accept that some complex systems and organs ''can'' be explained by evolution, they claim that organs and biological features which are ''irreducibly complex'' cannot be explained by current models, and that an intelligent designer must have created life or guided its evolution. Accordingly, the debate on irreducible complexity concerns two questions: whether irreducible complexity can be found in nature, and what significance it would have if it did exist in nature.{{Citation needed|date=January 2012}}

Behe's original examples of irreducibly complex mechanisms included the bacterial [[flagellum]] of ''[[Escherichia coli|E. coli]]'', [[coagulation|the blood clotting cascade]], [[cilia]], and the [[adaptive immune system]].

Behe argues that organs and biological features which are irreducibly complex cannot be wholly explained by current models of [[evolution]]. In explicating his definition of "irreducible complexity" he notes that:
<blockquote>An irreducibly complex system cannot be produced directly (that is, by continuously improving the initial function, which continues to work by the same mechanism) by slight, successive modifications of a precursor system, because any precursor to an irreducibly complex system that is missing a part is by definition nonfunctional.</blockquote>

Irreducible complexity is not an argument that evolution does not occur, but rather an argument that it is "incomplete". In the last chapter of ''[[Darwin's Black Box]]'', Behe goes on to explain his view that irreducible complexity is evidence for [[intelligent design]]. Mainstream critics, however, argue that irreducible complexity, as defined by Behe, can be generated by known evolutionary mechanisms. Behe's claim that no scientific literature adequately modeled the origins of biochemical systems through evolutionary mechanisms has been challenged by [[TalkOrigins Archive|TalkOrigins]].<ref>[http://www.talkorigins.org/indexcc/CA/CA350.html Claim CA350: Professional literature is silent on the subject of the evolution of biochemical systems] TalkOrigins Archive.</ref><ref>{{cite book |last= Behe |first= Michael J. |authorlink= Michael Behe |title= Darwin's black box: the biochemical challenge to evolution |isbn= 0-684-82754-9 |page= 72 |chapter= |quote= "Yet here again the evolutionary literature is totally missing. No scientist has ever published a model to account for the gradual evolution of this extraordinary molecular machine." |year= 1996 |publisher= Free Press |location= New York, NY |origyear= 1996}}</ref> The judge in the ''Dover'' trial wrote "By defining irreducible complexity in the way that he has, Professor Behe attempts to exclude the phenomenon of [[exaptation]] by definitional fiat, ignoring as he does so abundant evidence which refutes his argument. Notably, the [[United States National Academy of Sciences|NAS]] has rejected Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity..."<ref name=kitz74>[[s:Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District/4:Whether ID Is Science#Page 74 of 139|Ruling]], [[Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District]], December 2005. Page 74.</ref>

==Stated examples==
Behe and others have suggested a number of biological features that they believe may be irreducibly complex.

===Blood clotting cascade===
The process of blood clotting or [[coagulation]] cascade in vertebrates is a complex biological pathway which is given as an example of apparent irreducible complexity.<ref>Action, George [http://www.talkorigins.org/origins/postmonth/feb97.html "Behe and the Blood Clotting Cascade"]</ref>

The irreducible complexity argument assumes that the necessary parts of a system have always been necessary, and therefore could not have been added sequentially. However, in evolution, something which is at first merely advantageous can later become necessary.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Boudry |first=Maarten |authorlink=Maarten Boudry |last2=Blancke |first2=Stefaan |last3=Braeckman |first3=Johan |authorlink3=Johan Braeckman |title=Irreducible Incoherence and Intelligent Design: A Look into the Conceptual Toolbox of a Pseudoscience |journal=[[Quarterly Review of Biology]] |volume=85 |issue=3 |pages=473–82 |publisher= |date=September 2010 |url=http://sites.google.com/site/maartenboudry/irreducible-incoherence |issn= |doi=10.1086/656904 |accessdate= |pmid=21243965}}</ref> [[Natural selection]] can lead to complex biochemical systems being built up from simpler systems, or to existing functional systems being recombined as a new system with a different function.<ref name=kitz74/> For example, one of the clotting factors that Behe listed as a part of the clotting cascade ([[Factor XII]], also called Hageman factor) was later found to be absent in whales, demonstrating that it is not essential for a clotting system.<ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Semba U, Shibuya Y, Okabe H, Yamamoto T |title=Whale Hageman factor (factor XII): prevented production due to pseudogene conversion |journal=Thromb Res |year=1998 |pages=31–7 |volume=90 |issue=1 |pmid=9678675 |doi= 10.1016/S0049-3848(97)00307-1}}</ref> Many purportedly irreducible structures can be found in other organisms as much simpler systems that utilize fewer parts. These systems, in turn, may have had even simpler precursors that are now extinct. Behe has responded to critics of his clotting cascade arguments by suggesting that [[homology (biology)|homology]] is evidence for evolution, but not for natural selection.<ref>Behe, Michael [http://www.arn.org/docs/behe/mb_indefenseofbloodclottingcascade.htm "In Defense of the Irreducibility of the Blood Clotting Cascade: Response to Russell Doolittle, Ken Miller and Keith Robison"]</ref>

The "improbability argument" also misrepresents natural selection. It is correct to say that a set of simultaneous mutations that form a complex protein structure is so unlikely as to be unfeasible, but that is not what Darwin advocated. His explanation is based on small accumulated changes that take place without a final goal. Each step must be advantageous in its own right, although biologists may not yet understand the reason behind all of them—for example, [[jawless fish]] accomplish blood clotting with just six proteins instead of the full ten.<ref>[http://www.newscientist.com/article/mg18725073.800 Creationism special: A sceptic's guide to intelligent design], New Scientist, 9 July 2005</ref>

===Eye===
{{Main article|Evolution of the eye}}
[[File:Stages in the evolution of the eye.png|thumb|300px|Stages in the evolution of the eye<br/>(a) A pigment spot<br/>(b) A simple pigment cup<br/>(c) The simple optic cup found in [[abalone]]<br/>(d) The complex lensed eye of the marine snail and the octopus]]
The [[eye]] is an example of a supposedly irreducibly complex structure, due to its many elaborate and interlocking parts, seemingly all dependent upon one another. It is frequently cited by intelligent design and creationism advocates as an example of irreducible complexity. Behe used the "development of the eye problem" as evidence for intelligent design in ''Darwin's Black Box''. Although Behe acknowledged that the evolution of the larger anatomical features of the eye have been well-explained, he pointed out that the complexity of the minute biochemical reactions required at a molecular level for light sensitivity still defies explanation. Creationist [[Jonathan Sarfati]] has described the eye as evolutionary biologists' "greatest challenge as an example of superb 'irreducible complexity' in God's creation", specifically pointing to the supposed "vast complexity" required for transparency.<ref name="aig">[[Jonathan Sarfati|Sarfati, Jonathan]] (2000). [http://www.answersingenesis.org/home/area/re2/chapter10.asp Argument: 'Irreducible complexity'], from ''[[Refuting Evolution]]'' ([[Answers in Genesis]]).</ref>{{failed verification|redirects to http://www.answersingenesis.org/get-answers/topic/design-features, an unauthored blog|date=June 2012}}

In an often misquoted<ref>[http://www.talkorigins.org/indexcc/CA/CA113_1.html CA113.1: Evolution of the eye]</ref> passage from ''[[On the Origin of Species]]'', [[Charles Darwin]] appears to acknowledge the eye's development as a difficulty for his theory. However, the quote in context shows that Darwin actually had a very good understanding of the evolution of the eye (see [[fallacy of quoting out of context]]). He notes that "to suppose that the eye ... could have been formed by natural selection, seems, I freely confess, absurd in the highest possible degree". Yet this observation was merely a [[procatalepsis|rhetorical device]] for Darwin. He goes on to explain that if gradual evolution of the eye could be shown to be possible, "the difficulty of believing that a perfect and complex eye could be formed by natural selection ... can hardly be considered real". He then proceeded to roughly map out a likely course for evolution using examples of gradually more complex eyes of various species.<ref>[[Charles Darwin|Darwin, Charles]] (1859). ''[[The Origin of Species|On the Origin of Species]]''. London: John Murray. [http://darwin-online.org.uk/content/frameset?itemID=F373&viewtype=side&pageseq=204 pages 186ff, Chapter VI]</ref>

[[File:Evolution eye.svg|thumb|left|200px|The eyes of vertebrates (left) and invertebrates such as the [[octopus]] (right) developed independently: vertebrates evolved an inverted [[retina]] with a [[blind spot (vision)|blind spot]] over their [[optic disc]], whereas octopuses avoided this with a non-inverted retina.]]

Since Darwin's day, the eye's ancestry has become much better understood. Although learning about the construction of ancient eyes through fossil evidence is problematic due to the soft tissues leaving no imprint or remains, genetic and comparative anatomical evidence has increasingly supported the idea of a common ancestry for all eyes.<ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Halder G, Callaerts P, Gehring WJ |title=New perspectives on eye evolution |journal=Current Opinion in Genetics & Development |volume=5 |issue=5 |pages=602–9 |date=October 1995 |pmid=8664548 |url=http://linkinghub.elsevier.com/retrieve/pii/0959-437X(95)80029-8 |doi=10.1016/0959-437X(95)80029-8}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Halder G, Callaerts P, Gehring WJ |title=Induction of ectopic eyes by targeted expression of the eyeless gene in Drosophila |journal=Science |volume=267 |issue=5205 |pages=1788–92 |date=March 1995 |pmid=7892602 |url=http://www.sciencemag.org/cgi/pmidlookup?view=long&pmid=7892602 |doi=10.1126/science.7892602 |bibcode=1995Sci...267.1788H}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Tomarev SI, Callaerts P, Kos L, etal |title=Squid Pax-6 and eye development |journal=Proc Natl Acad Sci USA |volume=94 |issue=6 |pages=2421–6 |date=March 1997 |pmid=9122210 |pmc=20103 |url=http://www.pnas.org/cgi/pmidlookup?view=long&pmid=9122210 |doi=10.1073/pnas.94.6.2421 |bibcode=1997PNAS...94.2421T}}</ref>

Current evidence does suggest possible evolutionary lineages for the origins of the anatomical features of the eye. One likely chain of development is that the eyes originated as simple patches of [[photoreceptor cell]]s that could detect the presence or absence of light, but not its direction. When, via random mutation across the population, the photosensitive cells happened to have developed on a small depression, it endowed the organism with a better sense of the light's source. This small change gave the organism an advantage over those without the mutation. This genetic trait would then be "selected for" as those with the trait would have an increased chance of survival, and therefore progeny, over those without the trait. Individuals with deeper depressions would be able to discern changes in light over a wider field than those individuals with shallower depressions. As ever deeper depressions were advantageous to the organism, gradually, this depression would become a pit into which light would strike certain cells depending on its angle. The organism slowly gained increasingly precise visual information. And again, this gradual process continued as individuals having a slightly shrunken [[aperture]] of the eye had an advantage over those without the mutation as an aperture increases how [[collimated]] the light is at any one specific group of photoreceptors. As this trait developed, the eye became effectively a [[pinhole camera]] which allowed the organism to dimly make out shapes—the [[nautilus]] is a modern example of an animal with such an eye. Finally, via this same selection process, a protective layer of transparent cells over the aperture was differentiated into a crude [[lens (anatomy)|lens]], and the interior of the eye was filled with humours to assist in focusing images.<ref>Fernald, Russell D. (2001). [http://www.karger.com/gazette/64/fernald/art_1_1.htm The Evolution of Eyes: Why Do We See What We See?] ''Karger Gazette'' 64: "The Eye in Focus".</ref><ref>{{cite book |author=Fernald RD |chapter=Aquatic Adaptations in Fish Eyes |editor=Atema J |title=Sensory biology of aquatic animals |publisher=Springer-Verlag |location=Berlin |year=1988 |isbn=0-387-96373-1}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |author=Fernald RD |title=The evolution of eyes |journal=Brain Behav Evol. |volume=50 |issue=4 |pages=253–9 |year=1997 |pmid=9310200 |doi=10.1159/000113339}}</ref> In this way, eyes are recognized by modern biologists as actually a relatively unambiguous and simple structure to evolve, and many of the major developments of the eye's evolution are believed to have taken place over only a few million years, during the [[Cambrian explosion]].<ref>{{cite book |author=Conway-Morris S |title=The Crucible of Creation: The Burgess Shale and the Rise of Animals |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford [Oxfordshire] |year=1999 |pages= |isbn=0-19-286202-2}}</ref> Behe asserts that this is only an explanation of the gross anatomical steps, however, and not an explanation of the changes in discrete biochemical systems that would have needed to take place.<ref>{{Cite book|title=Darwin's Black Box|last=Behe|first=Michael|publisher=Free Press|year=2006|isbn=978-0-7432-9031-9|location=|pages=38}}</ref>

Behe maintains that the complexity of light sensitivity at the molecular level and the minute biochemical reactions required for those first "simple patches of photoreceptor[s]" still defies explanation, and that the proposed series of infinitesimal steps to get from patches of photoreceptors to a fully functional eye would actually be considered great, complex leaps in evolution if viewed on the molecular scale. Other intelligent design proponents claim that the evolution of the entire visual system would be difficult rather than the eye alone.<ref>{{cite book|title=A Meaningful World|year=2006|author1=Benjamin Wiker |author2=Jonathan Witt |page=44}}</ref>

===Flagella===
{{Main article|Evolution of flagella}}
The [[flagella]] of certain bacteria constitute a [[molecular motor]] requiring the interaction of about 40 different protein parts. Behe presents this as a prime example of an irreducibly complex structure defined as "a single system composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, wherein the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning", and argues that since "an irreducibly complex system that is missing a part is by definition nonfunctional", it could not have evolved gradually through [[natural selection]].<ref name="Flagellum Unspun"/>

'''Reducible complexity'''. In contrast to Behe's claims, many proteins can be deleted or mutated and the flagellum still works, even though sometimes at reduced efficiency.<ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Rajagopala SV, Titz B, Goll J, Parrish JR, Wohlbold K, McKevitt MT, Palzkill T, Mori H, ((Finley RL Jr)), Uetz P |year= 2007 |title= The protein network of bacterial motility |url= |journal= Mol Syst Biol. |volume= 3 |issue= |page= 128 |doi= 10.1038/msb4100166 |pmid= 17667950 |pmc=1943423}}</ref> In fact, the composition of flagella is surprisingly diverse across bacteria with many proteins only found in some species but not others.<ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Titz B, Rajagopala SV, Ester C, Häuser R, Uetz P |date= Nov 2006 |title= Novel conserved assembly factor of the bacterial flagellum |journal= J Bacteriol |volume= 188 |issue= 21 |pages= 7700–6 |doi= 10.1128/JB.00820-06 |pmid= 16936039 |pmc=1636259}}</ref> Hence the flagellar apparatus is clearly very flexible in evolutionary terms and perfectly able to lose or gain protein components. Further studies have shown that, contrary to claims of "irreducible complexity", flagella and related [[protein targeting|protein transport mechanisms]] show evidence of evolution through Darwinian processes, providing case studies in how complex systems can evolve from simpler components.<ref>{{cite journal |last1= Pallen |first1= M. J. |last2= Gophna |first2= U. |doi= 10.1159/000107602 |title= Bacterial Flagella and Type III Secretion: Case Studies in the Evolution of Complexity |journal= Gene and Protein Evolution |series= Genome Dynamics |volume= 3 |pages= 30–47 |year= 2007 |isbn= 3-8055-8340-0 |pmid= |pmc=}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1= Clements |first1= A. |last2= Bursac |first2= D. |last3= Gatsos |first3= X. |last4= Perry |first4= A. |last5= Civciristov |first5= S. |last6= Celik |first6= N. |last7= Likic |first7= V. |last8= Poggio |first8= S. |last9= Jacobs-Wagner |first9= C. |last10= Strugnell |first10= R. A. |last11= Lithgow |first11= T. |title= The reducible complexity of a mitochondrial molecular machine |journal= Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume= 106 |issue= 37 |pages= 15791–15795 |year= 2009 |pmid= 19717453 |pmc= 2747197 |doi= 10.1073/pnas.0908264106|bibcode= 2009PNAS..10615791C}}</ref> Multiple processes were involved in the evolution of the flagellum, including [[horizontal gene transfer]].<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Zuckerkandl|first1=Emile|title=Intelligent design and biological complexity|journal=Gene|date=December 2006|volume=385|pages=2–18|doi=10.1016/j.gene.2006.03.025|pmid=17011142}}</ref>

'''Evolution from Type Three Secretion Systems'''. Scientists regard this argument as having been disproved in the light of research dating back to 1996 as well as more recent findings.<ref name="Flagellum Unspun">Miller, Kenneth R. [http://www.millerandlevine.com/km/evol/design2/article.html The Flagellum Unspun: The Collapse of "Irreducible Complexity"] with reply here [http://www.designinference.com/documents/2003.02.Miller_Response.htm]</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Pallen |first1=M.J. |last2=Matzke |first2=N.J. |year=2006 |title=From ''The Origin of Species'' to the origin of bacterial flagella |journal=Nature Reviews Microbiology |volume=4 |issue= 10|pages=784–790 |publisher= |doi=10.1038/nrmicro1493 |url= |accessdate= |pmid=16953248}}</ref> They point out that the basal body of the flagella has been found to be similar to the [[Type three secretion system|Type III secretion system]] (TTSS), a needle-like structure that pathogenic germs such as ''[[Salmonella]]'' and ''[[Yersinia pestis]]'' use to inject [[toxin]]s into living [[eucaryote]] cells. The needle's base has ten elements in common with the flagellum, but it is missing forty of the proteins that make a flagellum work.<ref>[https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=RQQ7ubVIqo4 Kenneth Miller's The Collapse of Intelligent Design: Section 5 Bacterial Flagellum] (Case Western Reserve University, 2006 January 3)</ref> The TTSS system negates Behe's claim that taking away any one of the flagellum's parts would prevent the system from functioning. On this basis, [[Kenneth R. Miller|Kenneth Miller]] notes that, "The parts of this supposedly irreducibly complex system actually have functions of their own."<ref>[https://web.archive.org/web/20071010035647/http://debatebothsides.com/showthread.php?t=38338 Unlocking cell secrets bolsters evolutionists] (Chicago Tribune, 2006 February 13)</ref><ref>[http://www.talkdesign.org/faqs/flagellum.html Evolution in (Brownian) space: a model for the origin of the bacterial flagellum] (Talk Design, 2006 September)</ref> Studies have also shown that similar parts of the flagellum in different bacterial species can have different functions despite showing evidence of common descent, and that certain parts of the flagellum can be removed without completely eliminating its functionality.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Egelman|first1=E. H.|title=Intelligent Design A2 - Maloy, Stanley|journal=Brenner's Encyclopedia of Genetics (Second Edition)|date=1 January 2013|pages=112–114|url=http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/B9780123749840008068|publisher=Academic Press|doi=10.1016/B978-0-12-374984-0.00806-8}}</ref>

Dembski has argued that phylogenetically, the TTSS is found in a narrow range of bacteria which makes it seem to him to be a late innovation, whereas flagella are widespread throughout many bacterial groups, and he argues that it was an early innovation.<ref>[http://www.evolutionnews.org/2010/01/spinning_tales_about_the_bacte031141.html Spinning Tales About the Bacterial Flagellum]</ref><ref>Dembski, [http://www.designinference.com/documents/2005.09.Expert_Rebuttal_Dembski.pdf Rebuttal to Reports by Opposing Expert Witnesses, p. 52]</ref> Against Dembski's argument, different flagella use completely different mechanisms, and publications show a plausible path in which bacterial flagella could have evolved from a secretion system.<ref name="CB200.1:">{{cite web |last= Isaak |first= Mark |title= CB200.1: Bacterial flagella and Irreducibly Complexity |url= http://www.talkorigins.org/indexcc/CB/CB200_1.html |publisher= TalkOrigins Archive |year= 2006 |accessdate= 25 June 2013}}</ref>

===Biological wheels===
{{Main article|Rotating locomotion in living systems}}
The [[wheel]] is also stated as an irreducibly complex structure. Contrary to some other examples, its absence in nature has been said to provide evidence against intelligent design and creationism.<ref>
[http://www.livescience.com/22146-why-don-t-any-animals-have-wheels.html Why Don't Any Animals Have Wheels?]</ref> Molecular biologist [[Robin Holliday]] has written that the absence of biological wheels argues against [[creationism|creationist]] or [[intelligent design]] accounts of the diversity of life, because an intelligent creator—free of the limitations imposed by evolution—would be expected to deploy wheels wherever they would be of use.<ref name="Holliday">{{Cite journal | last = Holliday | first = Robin | authorlink = Robin Holliday | title = Creationism and the wheel | journal = BioEssays | volume = 25 | issue = 6 | pages = 620–621 | publisher = Wiley Periodicals | date = June 2003 | issn = 1521-1878 | doi = 10.1002/bies.10280| pmid = 12766952 }}</ref>

==Response of the scientific community==
Like intelligent design, the concept it seeks to support, irreducible complexity has failed to gain any notable acceptance within the [[scientific community]]. One science writer called it a "full-blown intellectual surrender strategy".<ref>Mirsky, Steve [http://www.sciam.com/article.cfm?articleID=00022DE1-0C15-11E6-B75283414B7F0000 Sticker Shock: In the beginning was the cautionary advisory] ''Scientific American'', February 2005</ref>

===Reducibility of "irreducible" systems===
Researchers have proposed potentially viable evolutionary pathways for allegedly irreducibly complex systems such as blood clotting, the immune system<ref>Matt Inlay, 2002. "[http://www.talkdesign.org/faqs/Evolving_Immunity.html Evolving Immunity]." In ''TalkDesign.org''.</ref> and the flagellum<ref>Nicholas J. Matzke, 2003. "[http://www.talkdesign.org/faqs/flagellum_background.html Evolution in (Brownian) space: a model for the origin of the bacterial flagellum]."</ref><ref>{{cite journal |vauthors=Pallen MJ, Matzke NJ |title= From The Origin of Species to the origin of bacterial flagella |journal= Nature Reviews Microbiology |volume= 4 |issue= 10 |pages= 784–90 |date= October 2006 |pmid= 16953248 |doi= 10.1038/nrmicro1493 |url= http://www.pandasthumb.org/archives/2006/09/flagellum_evolu.html}}</ref> - the three examples Behe proposed. John H. McDonald even showed his example of a mousetrap to be reducible.<ref name=trap/> If irreducible complexity is an insurmountable obstacle to evolution, it should not be possible to conceive of such pathways.<ref>Pigliucci, Massimo [http://www.infidels.org/library/modern/features/2000/pigliucci1.html] Collaboration Sept. 2001</ref>

Niall Shanks and Karl H. Joplin, both of [[East Tennessee State University]], have shown that systems satisfying Behe's characterization of irreducible biochemical complexity can arise naturally and spontaneously as the result of self-organizing chemical processes.<ref name="Redundant Complexity">{{cite journal |doi=10.1086/392687 |author1=Shanks, Niall |author2=Joplin, Karl H. |title=Redundant Complexity: A Critical Analysis of Intelligent Design in Biochemistry |journal=Philosophy of Science |year= 1999 |pages= 268–282 |volume= 66 |issue= 2, June |publisher=The University of Chicago Press |jstor=188646}}</ref><!--not working <ref>Niall Shanks and Karl H. Joplin. [http://www.asa3.org/ASA/topics/Apologetics/POS6-99ShenksJoplin.html Redundant Complexity:A Critical Analysis of Intelligent Design in Biochemistry.] East Tennessee State University.</ref>--> They also assert that what evolved biochemical and molecular systems actually exhibit is "redundant complexity"—a kind of complexity that is the product of an evolved biochemical process. They claim that Behe overestimated the significance of irreducible complexity because of his simple, linear view of biochemical reactions, resulting in his taking snapshots of selective features of biological systems, structures, and processes, while ignoring the redundant complexity of the context in which those features are naturally embedded. They also criticized his over-reliance of overly simplistic metaphors, such as his mousetrap.

A computer model of the co-evolution of proteins binding to DNA in the peer-reviewed journal ''[[Nucleic Acids Research]]'' consisted of several parts (DNA binders and DNA binding sites) which contribute to the basic function; removal of either one leads immediately to the death of the organism. This model fits the definition of irreducible complexity exactly, yet it evolves.<ref>{{cite journal |author=[[Thomas D. Schneider|Schneider TD]] |title=Evolution of Biological Information |journal= Nucleic Acids Research |year=2000 |pages=2794–2799 |volume=28 |issue=14 |pmid=10908337 |doi=10.1093/nar/28.14.2794 |pmc=102656}}</ref> (The program can be run from [http://alum.mit.edu/www/toms/papers/ev/ Ev program].)

In addition, research published in the peer-reviewed journal [[Nature (journal)|''Nature'']] has shown that computer simulations of evolution demonstrate that it is possible for complex features to evolve naturally.<ref>{{cite journal |author= [[Richard Lenski|Lenski RE]], Ofria C, Pennock RT, Adami C |title= The evolutionary origin of complex features |journal= Nature |year= 2003 |pages= 139–44 |volume= 423 |issue= 6936 |pmid= 12736677 |doi= 10.1038/nature01568|bibcode= 2003Natur.423..139L}}</ref>

One can compare a mousetrap with a cat in this context. Both normally function so as to control the mouse population. The cat has many parts that can be removed leaving it still functional; for example, its tail can be bobbed, or it can lose an ear in a fight. Comparing the cat and the mousetrap, then, one sees that the mousetrap (which is not alive) offers better evidence, in terms of irreducible complexity, for intelligent design than the cat. Even looking at the mousetrap analogy, several critics have described ways in which the parts of the mousetrap could have independent uses or could develop in stages, demonstrating that it is not irreducibly complex.<ref name=trap/><ref name=Only/>

Moreover, even cases where removing a certain component in an organic system will cause the system to fail do not demonstrate that the system could not have been formed in a step-by-step, evolutionary process. By analogy, stone arches are irreducibly complex&mdash;if you remove any stone the arch will collapse—yet humans [[arch#Construction|build them]] easily enough, one stone at a time, by building over [[centring|centering]] that is removed afterward. Similarly, [[natural arch|naturally occurring arches]] of stone form by the weathering away of bits of stone from a large concretion that has formed previously.

Evolution can act to simplify as well as to complicate. This raises the possibility that seemingly irreducibly complex biological features may have been achieved with a period of increasing complexity, followed by a period of simplification.

A team led by [[Joseph Thornton (biologist)|Joseph Thornton]], assistant professor of biology at the [[University of Oregon]]'s Center for Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, using techniques for resurrecting ancient genes, reconstructed the evolution of an apparently irreducibly complex molecular system. The April 7, 2006 issue of ''Science'' published this research.<ref name="thornton2006">{{cite journal |vauthors=Bridgham JT, Carroll SM, Thornton JW |title=Evolution of hormone-receptor complexity by molecular exploitation |journal=Science |volume=312 |issue=5770 |pages=97–101 |date=April 2006 |pmid=16601189 |doi=10.1126/science.1123348 |bibcode= 2006Sci...312...97B}}</ref><ref>[http://www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/filesDB-download.php?command=download&id=746 Press release] University of Oregon, April 4, 2006.</ref>

Irreducible complexity may not actually exist in nature, and the examples given by Behe and others may not in fact represent irreducible complexity, but can be explained in terms of simpler precursors. The theory of [[facilitated variation]] challenges irreducible complexity. [[Marc W. Kirschner]], a professor and chair of Department of Systems Biology at [[Harvard Medical School]], and [[John C. Gerhart]], a professor in Molecular and Cell Biology, [[University of California, Berkeley]], presented this theory in 2005. They describe how certain mutation and changes can cause apparent irreducible complexity. Thus, seemingly irreducibly complex structures are merely "very complex", or they are simply misunderstood or misrepresented.

===Gradual adaptation to new functions===
{{Main article|Exaptation}}
The precursors of complex systems, when they are not useful in themselves, may be useful to perform other, unrelated functions. Evolutionary biologists argue that evolution often works in this kind of blind, haphazard manner in which the function of an early form is not necessarily the same as the function of the later form. The term used for this process is [[exaptation]]. The [[evolution of mammalian auditory ossicles|mammalian middle ear]] (derived from a jawbone) and the [[giant panda|panda]]'s thumb (derived from a wrist bone spur) provide classic examples. A 2006 article in ''Nature'' demonstrates intermediate states leading toward the development of the ear in a [[Devonian]] fish (about 360 million years ago).<ref>{{cite journal |journal= Nature |volume= 439 |pages= 318–21 |date= January 19, 2006 |author1=M. Brazeau |author2=P. Ahlberg |doi= 10.1038/nature04196 |issue= 7074 |title= Tetrapod-like middle ear architecture in a Devonian fish |pmid= 16421569|bibcode= 2006Natur.439..318B}}</ref> Furthermore, recent research shows that viruses play a heretofore unexpected role in evolution by mixing and matching genes from various hosts.{{Citation needed|date=November 2009}}

Arguments for irreducibility often assume that things started out the same way they ended up&mdash;as we see them now. However, that may not necessarily be the case. In the ''Dover'' trial an expert witness for the plaintiffs, Ken Miller, demonstrated this possibility using Behe's mousetrap analogy. By removing several parts, Miller made the object unusable as a mousetrap, but he pointed out that it was now a perfectly functional, if unstylish, [[tie clip]].<ref name=Only/><ref name=NOVAChapter8>{{cite web |url= http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/nova/transcripts/3416_id_08.html |title=NOVA: Transcripts: Judgment Day: Intelligent Design on Trial Chapter 8 |date= November 13, 2007 |publisher= [[Public Broadcasting Service|PBS]] |accessdate= 2008-12-17}}</ref>

===Methods by which irreducible complexity may evolve===
Irreducible complexity can be seen as equivalent to crossing a "valley" in a [[fitness landscape]]. A number of mathematical models of evolution have explored the circumstances under which this can happen.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Weissman|first1=Daniel B.|last2=Desai|first2=Michael M.|last3=Fisher|first3=Daniel S.|last4=Feldman|first4=Marcus W.|title=The rate at which asexual populations cross fitness valleys|journal=Theoretical Population Biology|date=June 2009|volume=75|issue=4|pages=286–300|doi=10.1016/j.tpb.2009.02.006}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Weissman|first1=D. B.|last2=Feldman|first2=M. W.|last3=Fisher|first3=D. S.|title=The Rate of Fitness-Valley Crossing in Sexual Populations|journal=Genetics|date=5 October 2010|volume=186|issue=4|pages=1389–1410|doi=10.1534/genetics.110.123240|pmid=20923976|pmc=2998319}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Trotter|first1=Meredith V.|last2=Weissman|first2=Daniel B.|last3=Peterson|first3=Grant I.|last4=Peck|first4=Kayla M.|last5=Masel|first5=Joanna|title=Cryptic genetic variation can make "irreducible complexity" a common mode of adaptation in sexual populations|journal=Evolution|date=December 2014|volume=68|issue=12|pages=3357–3367|doi=10.1111/evo.12517|pmid=25178652|pmc=4258170}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Covert|first1=Arthur|last2=Lenski|first2=Richard|last3=Wilke|first3=Claus|last4=Ofria|first4=Charles|title=Experiments on the role of deleterious mutations as stepping stones in adaptive evolution|journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences|date=2013|volume=110|issue=34|pages=E3171-E3178|doi=10.1073/pnas.1313424110|pmid=23918358|pmc=3752215}}</ref>

===Falsifiability and experimental evidence===
Some critics, such as [[Jerry Coyne]] (professor of [[evolutionary biology]] at the [[University of Chicago]]) and [[Eugenie Scott]] (a [[physical anthropology|physical anthropologist]] and former executive director of the [[National Center for Science Education]]) have argued that the concept of irreducible complexity and, more generally, [[intelligent design]] is not [[falsifiability|falsifiable]] and, therefore, not [[scientific]].

Behe argues that the theory that irreducibly complex systems could not have evolved can be falsified by an experiment where such systems are evolved. For example, he posits taking bacteria with no [[flagella|flagellum]] and imposing a selective pressure for mobility. If, after a few thousand generations, the bacteria evolved the bacterial flagellum, then Behe believes that this would refute his theory.{{Citation needed|date=May 2009}}

Other critics take a different approach, pointing to experimental evidence that they believe falsifies the argument for Intelligent Design from irreducible complexity. For example, [[Kenneth R. Miller|Kenneth Miller]] cites the lab work of Barry G. Hall on [[Escherichia coli|E. coli]], which he asserts is evidence that "Behe is wrong".<ref>{{cite book |author= Miller K |title= Finding Darwin's God: a scientist's search for common ground between God and evolution |publisher= Cliff Street Books |location= New York |year= 1999 |isbn= 0-06-093049-7}}</ref>

Other evidence that irreducible complexity is not a problem for evolution comes from the field of [[computer science]], which routinely uses computer analogues of the processes of evolution in order to automatically design complex solutions to problems. The results of such [[genetic algorithm]]s are frequently irreducibly complex since the process, like evolution, both removes non-essential components over time as well as adding new components. The removal of unused components with no essential function, like the natural process where rock underneath a [[natural arch]] is removed, can produce irreducibly complex structures without requiring the intervention of a designer. Researchers applying these algorithms automatically produce human-competitive designs—but no human designer is required.<ref>[http://www.genetic-programming.com/humancompetitive.html 36 Human-Competitive Results Produced by Genetic Programming]</ref>

===Argument from ignorance===
Intelligent design proponents attribute to an intelligent designer those biological structures they believe are irreducibly complex and therefore they say a natural explanation is insufficient to account for them.<ref>Michael Behe. [http://www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=51 Evidence for Intelligent Design from Biochemistry.] 1996.</ref> However, critics view irreducible complexity as a special case of the "complexity indicates design" claim, and thus see it as an [[argument from ignorance]] and as a [[God of the gaps|God-of-the-gaps]] argument.<ref name="isaak_ci101">Index to Creationist Claims. Mark Isaak. The Talk.Origins Archive. "Irreducible complexity and complex specified information are special cases of the "complexity indicates design" claim; they are also arguments from incredulity." [http://www.talkorigins.org/indexcc/CI/CI101.html] "The argument from incredulity creates a god of the gaps." [http://www.talkorigins.org/indexcc/CA/CA100.html]</ref>

[[Eugenie Scott]], along with [[Glenn Branch]] and other critics, has argued that many points raised by intelligent-design proponents are arguments from ignorance.<ref>[[Eugenie C. Scott]] and Glenn Branch, [http://ncseweb.org/creationism/general/intelligent-design-not-accepted-by-most-scientists "Intelligent Design" Not Accepted by Most Scientists], National Center for Science Education website, September 10, 2002.</ref> Behe has been accused by critics <ref>Patheos.com essay: An argument premised on the author's lack of imagination.[http://www.patheos.com/blogs/daylightatheism/essays/darwins-black-box/]</ref><ref>Amerikanbeat.net: A Critique of Behe, Dembski on "Irreducible Complexity"[http://amerikanbeat.net/contact-amerikanbeat/a-critique-of-behe-dembski-on-%E2%80%9Cirreducible-complexity%E2%80%9D/]</ref> of using an "argument by lack of imagination".

===False dilemma===
Irreducible complexity is at its core an argument against evolution. If truly irreducible systems are found, the argument goes, then [[intelligent design]] must be the correct explanation for their existence. However, this conclusion is based on the assumption that current [[evolution]]ary theory and intelligent design are the only two valid models to explain life, a [[false dilemma]].<ref>[http://www.talkdesign.org/faqs/icdmyst/ICDmyst.html IC and Evolution] makes the point that: if "irreducible complexity" is tautologically redefined to allow a valid argument that [[intelligent design]] is the correct explanation for life then there is no such thing as "irreducible complexity" in the mechanisms of life; while, if we use the unmodified original definition then "irreducible complexity" has nothing whatever to do with evolution.</ref><ref>The Court in ''[[Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District|Dover]]'' noted that this implicit assumption of the defendant school board created a "flawed and illogical contrived dualism" (Opinion p. 64).</ref>

==Irreducible complexity in the Dover trial==
While testifying during the 2005 ''[[Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District]]'' trial, Behe conceded that there are no peer-reviewed papers supporting his claims that complex molecular systems, like the bacterial flagellum, the blood-clotting cascade, and the immune system, were intelligently designed nor are there any peer-reviewed articles supporting his argument that certain complex molecular structures are "irreducibly complex."<ref name="Kitzmiller_ruling_ID_science"/>

In the final ruling of ''Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District'', Judge Jones specifically singled out Behe and irreducible complexity:<ref name=Kitzmiller_ruling_ID_science>[[s:Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District/4:Whether ID Is Science|Memorandum Opinion, Judge John E. Jones III, Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District]]</ref>
*"Professor Behe admitted in "Reply to My Critics" that there was a defect in his view of irreducible complexity because, while it purports to be a challenge to natural selection, it does not actually address "the task facing natural selection." and that "Professor Behe wrote that he hoped to "repair this defect in future work..." (Page 73)
*"As expert testimony revealed, the qualification on what is meant by "irreducible complexity" renders it meaningless as a criticism of evolution. (3:40 (Miller)). In fact, the theory of evolution proffers exaptation as a well-recognized, well-documented explanation for how systems with multiple parts could have evolved through natural means." (Page 74)
*"By defining irreducible complexity in the way that he has, Professor Behe attempts to exclude the phenomenon of exaptation by definitional fiat, ignoring as he does so abundant evidence which refutes his argument. Notably, the [[United States National Academy of Sciences|NAS]] has rejected Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity..." (Page 75)
*"As irreducible complexity is only a negative argument against evolution, it is refutable and accordingly testable, unlike ID [Intelligent Design], by showing that there are intermediate structures with selectable functions that could have evolved into the allegedly irreducibly complex systems. (2:15-16 (Miller)). Importantly, however, the fact that the negative argument of irreducible complexity is testable does not make testable the argument for ID. (2:15 (Miller); 5:39 (Pennock)). Professor Behe has applied the concept of irreducible complexity to only a few select systems: (1) the bacterial flagellum; (2) the blood-clotting cascade; and (3) the immune system. Contrary to Professor Behe's assertions with respect to these few biochemical systems among the myriad existing in nature, however, Dr. Miller presented evidence, based upon peer-reviewed studies, that they are not in fact irreducibly complex." (Page 76)
*"...on cross-examination, Professor Behe was questioned concerning his 1996 claim that science would never find an evolutionary explanation for the immune system. He was presented with fifty-eight peer-reviewed publications, nine books, and several immunology textbook chapters about the evolution of the immune system; however, he simply insisted that this was still not sufficient evidence of evolution, and that it was not "good enough." (23:19 (Behe))." (Page 78)
*"We therefore find that Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity has been refuted in peer-reviewed research papers and has been rejected by the scientific community at large. (17:45-46 (Padian); 3:99 (Miller)). Additionally, even if irreducible complexity had not been rejected, it still does not support ID as it is merely a test for evolution, not design. (2:15, 2:35-40 (Miller); 28:63-66 (Fuller)). We will now consider the purportedly "positive argument" for design encompassed in the phrase used numerous times by Professors Behe and Minnich throughout their expert testimony, which is the "purposeful arrangement of parts." Professor Behe summarized the argument as follows: We infer design when we see parts that appear to be arranged for a purpose. The strength of the inference is quantitative; the more parts that are arranged, the more intricately they interact, the stronger is our confidence in design. The appearance of design in aspects of biology is overwhelming. Since nothing other than an intelligent cause has been demonstrated to be able to yield such a strong appearance of design, Darwinian claims notwithstanding, the conclusion that the design seen in life is real design is rationally justified. (18:90-91, 18:109-10 (Behe); 37:50 (Minnich)). As previously indicated, this argument is merely a restatement of the [[William Paley|Reverend William Paley]]'s argument applied at the cell level. Minnich, Behe, and Paley reach the same conclusion, that complex organisms must have been designed using the same reasoning, except that Professors Behe and Minnich refuse to identify the designer, whereas Paley inferred from the presence of design that it was God. (1:6- 7 (Miller); 38:44, 57 (Minnich)). Expert testimony revealed that this inductive argument is not scientific and as admitted by Professor Behe, can never be ruled out. (2:40 (Miller); 22:101 (Behe); 3:99 (Miller))." (Pages 79–80)

==Notes and references==
{{Reflist|30em}}

==Additional references==
*{{cite book |last= Behe |first= Michael |year= 1996 |title= [[Darwin's Black Box]] |location= New York |publisher= The Free Press |isbn= 0-684-83493-6 |oclc= 34150540 |ref= harv}}
*{{cite book |last= Denton |first= Michael |title= [[Evolution: A Theory in Crisis]] |publisher= Adler & Adler |location= Bethesda, Md |year= 1986 |isbn= 0-917561-05-8 |ref= harv}}
*{{cite journal |author=Macnab RM |title=Type III flagellar protein export and flagellar assembly |journal=Biochim Biophys Acta |year=2004 |pages=207–17 |volume=1694 |issue=1–3 |pmid=15546667 |doi=10.1016/j.bbamcr.2004.04.005}}
*{{cite journal|author1=Ruben, J.A. |author2=Jones, T.D. |author3=Geist, N.R. |author4=Hillenius, W.J. |date=November 14, 1997|title=Lung Structure and Ventilation in Theropod Dinosaurs and Early Birds |journal=Science |volume=278 |issue=5341 |pages=1267–70 |doi=10.1126/science.278.5341.1267|bibcode= 1997Sci...278.1267R}}
*Sunderland, Luther D. (March 1976). Miraculous Design in Woodpeckers. ''Creation Research Society Quarterly''.
*[http://www.carlzimmer.com/articles/2005/articles_2005_Avida.html Testing Darwin] [[Discover Magazine]] [http://www.discovermagazine.com/issues/feb-05/cover/ Vol. 26 No. 02] |February 2005

==External links==
;Supportive
*[http://www.arn.org/authors/behe.html Michael J. Behe home page]
*[http://www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=3408&program=DI%20Main%20Page%20-%20News&callingPage=discoMainPage About Irreducible Complexity] [[Discovery Institute]]
*[http://www.iscid.org/papers/Behe_ReplyToCritics_121201.pdf Behe's Reply to his Critics] (pdf)
*[http://www.discovery.org/scripts/viewDB/index.php?command=view&id=3419 How to Explain Irreducible Complexity -- A Lab Manual] [[Discovery Institute]]
*[http://www.icr.org/pdf/af/af0312.pdf Institute for Creation Research] (pdf)
* [http://www.asa3.org/ASA/education/origins/ic-cr.htm Irreducible Complexity: Definition & Evaluation] by Craig Rusbult, Ph.D.
*[http://www.iscid.org/papers/Dembski_IrreducibleComplexityRevisited_011404.pdf Irreducible Complexity Revisited] (pdf)

;Critical
*[http://www.pdcnet.org/collection/show?id=philo_2001_0004_0001_0054_0067&file_type=pdf Behe, Biochemistry, and the Invisible Hand]
*[http://bostonreview.net/archives/BR21.6/orr.html Darwin vs. Intelligent Design (again), by H. Allen Orr (review of Darwin's Black Box)]
*[http://www.newyorker.com/magazine/2005/05/30/devolution-2 Devolution: Why intelligent design isn't] ([[The New Yorker]])
*[http://www.talkreason.org/articles/Suboptimal.cfm Does irreducible complexity imply Intelligent Design?] by Mark Perakh
*[http://www.pbs.org/wgbh/evolution/library/01/1/l_011_01.html Evolution of the Eye (Video)] Zoologist Dan-Erik Nilsson demonstrates eye evolution through intermediate stages with working model. ([[Public Broadcasting Service|PBS]])
*[http://yalepress.yale.edu/yupbooks/book.asp?isbn=0300108656 Facilitated Variation]
*[[Kenneth Einar Himma|Himma, Kenneth Einar]]. [http://www.iep.utm.edu/d/design.htm Design Arguments for the Existence of God]. ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'': 2. Contemporary Versions of the Design Argument, a. The Argument from Irreducible Biochemical Complexity
*[http://ncse.com/creationism/legal/kitzmiller-trial-transcripts Kitzmiller vs. Dover transcripts]
*[http://www.millerandlevine.com Miller, Kenneth R. textbook website]
*[http://www.millerandlevine.com/km/evol/design2/article.html Miller's "The Flagellum Unspun: The Collapse of Irreducible Complexity"]
*[http://www.talkorigins.org Talk.origins archive] (see [[talk.origins]])
*[http://www.talkdesign.org TalkDesign.org] (sister site to talk.origins archive on [[intelligent design]])
*[http://www.abc.net.au/science/articles/2015/07/07/4251468.htm The bacterial flagellar motor: brilliant evolution or intelligent design?] Matt Baker, [[Australian Broadcasting Corporation|ABC]] Science, 7 July 2015
*[http://articles.chicagotribune.com/2006-02-13/news/0602130210_1_intelligent-design-michael-behe-dover-case Unlocking cell secrets bolsters evolutionists] ([[Chicago Tribune]])



{{DEFAULTSORT:Irreducible Complexity}}
[[Category:Creationist objections to evolution]]
[[Category:Intelligent design]]
[[Category:Biological systems]]
[[Category:Complex systems theory]]
[[Category:Pseudoscience]]

০৮:০৩, ২২ জুলাই ২০১৭ তারিখে সংশোধিত সংস্করণ

সমকামিতা ও মনোবিজ্ঞান

Historical background

The view of homosexuality as a psychological disorder has been seen in literature since research on homosexuality first began; however, psychology as a discipline has evolved over the years in its position on homosexuality. Current attitudes have their roots in religious, legal and cultural underpinnings. In the early Middle Ages the Christian Church ignored homosexuality in secular society; however, by the end of the 12th century hostility towards homosexuality began to emerge and spread through Europe’s secular and religious institutions. There were official expressions condemning the "unnatural" nature of homosexual behavior in the works of Thomas Aquinas and others. Until the 19th century, homosexual activity was referred to as "unnatural, crimes against nature", sodomy or buggery and was punishable by law, sometimes by death.[১] As people became more interested in discovering the causes of homosexuality, medicine and psychiatry began competing with the law and religion for jurisdiction. In the beginning of the 19th century, people began studying homosexuality scientifically. At this time, most theories regarded homosexuality as a disease, which had a great influence on how it was viewed culturally.[২] There was a paradigm shift in the mid 20th century in psychiatric science in regards to theories of homosexuality. Psychiatrists began to believe homosexuality could be cured through therapy and freedom of self, and other theories about the genetic and hormonal origin of homosexuality were becoming accepted. There were variations of how homosexuality was viewed as pathological.[১] Some early psychiatrists such as Sigmund Freud and Havelock Ellis adopted more tolerant stances on homosexuality. Freud and Ellis believed that homosexuality was not normal, but was "unavoidable" for some people. Alfred Kinsey's research and publications about homosexuality began the social and cultural shift away from viewing homosexuality as an abnormal condition. These shifting viewpoints in the psychological studies of homosexuality are evident in its placement in the first version of the Diagnostic Statistical Manual (DSM) in 1952, and subsequent change in 1973, in which the diagnosis of ego-dystonic homosexuality replaced the DSM-II category of "sexual orientation disturbance."[২] However, it was not until 1987 in DSM-III-R that it was entirely dropped as a mental disorder.

Freud and psychoanalysis

Sigmund Freud's views on homosexuality were complex. In his attempts to understand the causes and development of homosexuality, he first explained bisexuality as an "original libido endowment,"[৩] by which he meant that all humans are born bisexual. He believed that the libido has a homosexual portion and a heterosexual portion, and through the course of development one wins out over the other. He also believed in a basic biological explanation for natural bisexuality in which humans are all biologically capable of being aroused by either sex. Because of this he described homosexuality as one of many sexual options available to people. Freud proposed that humans' inherent bisexuality leads individuals to eventually choose which expression of sexuality is more gratifying, but because of cultural taboos homosexuality is repressed in many people. According to Freud, if there were no taboos people would choose whichever was more gratifying to them- and this could remain fluid throughout life- sometimes a person would be homosexual, sometimes heterosexual.[৪]

Some other causes of homosexuality for which he advocated included an inverted Oedipus complex where individuals begin to identify with their mother and take themselves as a love object. This love of one's self is defined as narcissism, and Freud thought that people who were high in the trait of narcissism would be more likely to develop homosexuality because loving the same sex is like an extension of loving oneself.[৪] The connection between narcissism and Homosexuality was later supported by an empirical study made by Rubinstein (2010). The results of the study indicated that homosexual students score higher in two measures of narcissism and lower on a self-esteem measure, compared to their heterosexual counterparts.[৫]

Freud believed treatment of homosexuality was not successful because the individual does not want to give up their homosexual identity because it brings them pleasure. He used analysis and hypnotic suggestion as treatments, but showed little success.[৬] It was through this that Freud arrived at the conclusion that homosexuality was "nothing to be ashamed of, no vice, no degradation, it cannot be classified as an illness, but a variation of sexual function."[৭] He further stated that psychoanalysts "should not promise to abolish homosexuality and make normal heterosexuality take its place,"[৩] as he had concluded in his own practice that attempts to change homosexual orientations were likely to be unsuccessful. While Freud himself may have come to a more accepting view of homosexuality, his legacy in the field of psychoanalysis, especially in the United States viewed homosexuality as negative, abnormal and caused by family and developmental issues. It was these views that significantly impacted the rationale for putting homosexuality in the first and second publications of the American Psychiatric Association's DSM, conceptualizing it as a mental disorder and further stigmatizing homosexuality in society.[২]

Havelock Ellis

Havelock Ellis (1859-1939) was working as a teacher in Australia, when he had a revelation that he wanted to dedicate his life to exploring the issue of sexuality. He returned to London in 1879 and enrolled in St. Thomas’s Hospital Medical School. He began to write, and in 1896 he co-authored Sexual Inversion with John Addington Symonds, his then lover of 6 months. The book was first published in German, and a year later it was translated into English. Their book explored homosexual relationships, and in a progressive approach for their time they refused to criminalize or pathologize the acts and emotions that were present in homosexual relationships.[৮]

Ellis disagreed with Freud on a few points regarding homosexuality, especially regarding its development. He argued that homosexuals do not have a clear cut Oedipus complex but they do have strong feelings of inadequacy, born of fears of failure and may also be afraid of relations with women.[৯] Ellis argued that the restrictions of society contributed to the development of same-sex love. He believed that homosexuality is not something people are born with, but that at some point humans are all sexually indiscriminant, and then narrow down and choose which sex acts to stick with. According to Ellis, some people choose to engage in homosexuality, while others will choose heterosexuality.[৯] He proposed that being “exclusively homosexual” [১০] is to be deviant because the person is a member of a minority and therefore statistically unusual, but that society should accept that deviations from the "normal" were harmless, and maybe even valuable.[৮] Ellis believed that psychological problems arose not from homosexual acts alone, but when someone "psychologically harms himself by fearfully limiting his own sex behavior."[৯]

Ellis is often attributed with coining the term homosexuality but in reality he despised the word because it conflated Latin and Greek roots and instead used the term invert in his published works. Soon after Sexual Inversion was published in England it was banned as lewd and scandalous. Ellis argued that homosexuality was a characteristic of a minority, and was not acquired or a vice and was not curable. He advocated changing the laws to leave those who chose to practice homosexuality at peace, because at the time it was a punishable crime. He believed societal reform could occur, but only after the public was educated. His book became a landmark in the understanding of homosexuality.[৮]

Alfred Kinsey

Alfred Charles Kinsey (1894-1956) was a sexologist who founded the Institute for Sex Research, which is now known as the Kinsey Institute for Research in Sex, Gender and Reproduction. His explorations into different sexual practices originated from his study of the variations in mating practices among wasps. He developed the Kinsey Scale, which measures sexual orientation in ranges from 0 to 6 with 0 being exclusively heterosexual and 6 being exclusively homosexual.[১১] His findings indicated that there was great variability in sexual orientations. Kinsey published books titled Sexual Behavior in the Human Male, and Sexual Behavior in the Human Female, which brought him a lot of fame and controversy. The prevailing approach to homosexuality at the time was to pathologize and attempt to change homosexuals. Kinsey's book demonstrated that homosexuality was more common than was assumed, suggesting that these behaviors are normal and part of a continuum of sexual behaviors.[২]

The Diagnostic and Statistical Manual

The social, medical and legal approach to homosexuality ultimately led for its inclusion in the first and second publications of the American Psychiatric Association’s Diagnostic and Statistical Manual (DSM). This served to conceptualize homosexuality as a mental disorder and further stigmatize homosexuality in society. However, the evolution in scientific study and empirical data from Kinsey, Evelyn Hooker and others confronted these beliefs, and by the 1970s psychiatrists and psychologists were radically altering their views on homosexuality. Tests such as the Rorschach, Thematic Apperception Test (TAT) and the Minnesota Multiphasic Personality Inventory (MMPI) indicated that homosexual men and women were not distinguishable from heterosexual men and women in functioning. These studies failed to support the previous assumptions that family dynamics, trauma and gender identity were factors in the development of sexual orientation. Due to lack of supporting data, as well as exponentially increasing pressure from the advocates of homosexuality, the Board of Directors for the American Psychiatric Association voted to remove homosexuality as a mental disorder from the DSM in 1973.[২] See DSM-III. After considerable delay and controversy, DSM-III-R (1987) dropped homosexuality as a listed mental disorder.[তথ্যসূত্র প্রয়োজন]

Major areas of psychological research

Causes of homosexuality

Numerous different theories have been proposed to explain the development of homosexuality, but there is so far no universally accepted account of the origins of a homosexual sexual orientation.[১২]

বৈষম্য

সমকামি বিরোধী এ মনোভাব এবং আচরণ ( যাকে মাঝে মাঝে 'হোমোফোবিয়া' বা 'হেটোরোসেক্সুয়াল' নামে অভিহিত করা হয়) মনস্তাত্ত্বিক গবেষণাগুলির একটি বিষয় হয়ে দাঁড়িয়েছে। এই ধরনের গবেষণাগুলোতে; সমাজে নারী সমকামির তুলনায় পুরুষ সমকামীদের প্রতি যে বৈরী আচরণ সচরাচর পরিলক্ষিত হয়, তাই ফুটে উঠেছে।[১৩] যারা সমকামীদের ব্যক্তিগত ভাবে জানে না, সমকামী-বিরোধী মনোভাব মুলত তাদের মধ্যেই দেখা যায়।[১৪] There is also a high risk for anti-gay bias in psychotherapy with lesbian, gay, and bisexual clients.[১৫]এক গবেষণায় দেখা গেছে যে, প্রায় অর্ধেক নমুনা মৌখিকভাবে বা শারীরিক সহিংসতার শিকার ছিল কারণ তাদের যৌন অভিযোজন, সাধারণত পুরুষদের দ্বারা সংঘটিত হয়। এই ধরনের হয়রানি হতাশা, উদ্বেগ, ক্রোধ, এবং পোস্ট ট্রমাটিক চাপের উপসর্গগুলির উচ্চ স্তরের সাথে সম্পর্কিত One study found that nearly half of its sample had been the victim of verbal or physical violence because of their sexual orientation, usually committed by men. Such victimization is related to higher levels of depression, anxiety, anger, and symptoms of post-traumatic stress.[১৬] Research suggests that parents who respond negatively to their child's sexual orientation tended to have lower self-esteem and negative attitudes toward women, and that "negative feelings about homosexuality in parents decreased the longer they were aware of their child's homosexuality."[১৭]

উপরন্তু, গবেষণায় প্রস্তাবনা করা হয়েছে যে, "যেসব পরিবার তাদের পারিবারিক ঐতিহ্যগত মূল্যবোধ অনুসরণ করে, ধর্মীয় রীতিনীতি অনুসরণ করে, বিবাহ এবং বাচ্চাকাচ্চা থাকার প্রতি জোর দেয়, সেসব পরিবারের; কম ঐতিহ্য অনুসরণ করা পরিবারের তুলনায়; সমকামিতাকে গ্রহণ করার মানসিকতা কম দেখা যায়।"[১৮] তবে আরো একটি গবেষণা থেকে দেখা গিয়েছে, এটি সর্বজনীন নয়। অর্থাৎ এর উল্টোটাও হতে পারে। উদাহরণস্বরূপ, চানা এটেনংফ এবং কোলেট ডাইয়েট কর্তৃক APA's Psychology of Religion & Spirituality নামক জার্নালে একটি গবেষণা প্রকাশিত হয়। সেখানে দেখা গেছে যে; ধর্মীয় পরিবারের সদস্যরা উল্টো তাদের কোনো সদস্যের ভিন্ন যৌন অভিমুখিতাকে ধর্মীয় মুল্যবোধ ও ধর্মীয় গ্রন্থ দ্বারাই স্বীকার বা সমর্থন করছেন। যেমনঃ একজন ক্যাথলিক মা, তার সমকামি পুত্রের অভিব্যক্তি নিয়ে কথা বলতে গিয়ে বলেন, "স্রষ্টার সকল নির্দেশনার উপরে নির্দেশনা হলো ভালোবাসা"। একইভাবে একজন মেথোডিস্ট মা তার প্রিয় সমকামী পুত্রের সাথে এবিষয়ে কথা বলতে গিয়ে যীশুকেই তথ্যসুত্র হিসেবে ব্যবহার করেন। তিনি বলেন, "আমি যীশাসের বার্তা পড়ি, তার বার্তায় তিনি ভালোবাসার কথা বলেছেন, ক্ষমার কথা বলেছেন, এবং আমি মনে করি না, একজন লোককে কখনোই তার ভালোবাসামুলক কাজের জন্য শাস্তি দেওয়া যায়।।" একই বক্তব্য প্রতিফলিত হয়েছে একজন ধার্মিক মরমন পিতার দ্বারা, তিনি বলেছেন, "যদি তুমি কাওকে ভালোবাসো, তাহলে সেটা স্বীকার করে নেওয়াই সবচেয়ে বেশি যৌক্তিক।"[১৯]”.

Mental health issues

Psychological research in this area includes examining mental health issues (including stress, depression, or addictive behavior) faced by gay and lesbian people as a result of the difficulties they experience because of their sexual orientation, physical appearance issues, eating disorders, or gender atypical behavior.

  • Psychiatric disorders: In a Dutch study, gay men reported significantly higher rates of mood and anxiety disorders than straight men, and lesbians were significantly more likely to experience depression (but not other mood or anxiety disorders) than straight women.[২০]
  • Physical appearance and eating disorders: Gay men tend to be more concerned about their physical appearance than straight men.[২১] Lesbian women are at a lower risk for eating disorders than heterosexual women.[২২]
  • Gender atypical behavior: While this is not a disorder, gay men may face difficulties due to being more likely to display gender atypical behavior than heterosexual men.[২৩] The difference is less pronounced between lesbians and straight women.[২৪]
  • Minority stress: Stress caused from a sexual stigma, manifested as prejudice and discrimination, is a major source of stress for people with a homosexual orientation. Sexual-minority affirming groups and gay peer groups help counteract and buffer minority stress.[২৫]
  • Ego-dystonic sexual orientation: Conflict between religious identity and sexual orientation identity can cause severe stress, causing some people to want to change their sexual orientation. Sexual orientation identity exploration can help individuals evaluate the reasons behind the desire to change and help them resolve the conflict between their religious and sexual identity, either through sexual orientation identity reconstruction or affirmation therapies. Therapists are to offer acceptance, support, and understanding of clients and the facilitation of clients’ active coping, social support, and identity exploration and development, without imposing a specific sexual orientation identity outcome.[২৫] Ego-dystonic sexual orientation is a disorder where a person wishes their sexual orientation were different because of associated psychological and behavioral disorders.
  • Sexual relationship disorder: People with a homosexual orientation in mixed-orientation marriages may struggle with the fear of the loss of their marriage. Therapists should focus exploring the underlying personal and contextual problems, motivations, realities, and hopes for being in, leaving, or restructuring the relationship and should not focus solely on one outcome such as divorce or marriage.[২৫] Sexual relationship disorder is a disorder where the gender identity or sexual orientation interferes with maintaining or forming of a relationship.

Suicide

The likelihood of suicide attempts is higher in both gay males and lesbians, as well as bisexual individuals of both sexes, when compared to their heterosexual counterparts.[২৬][২৭][২৮] The trend of having a higher incident rate among females encompasses lesbians or bisexual females; when compared with homosexual or bisexual males, lesbians are more likely to attempt suicide.[২৯]

Studies dispute the exact difference in suicide rate compared to heterosexuals with a minimum of 0.8–1.1 times more likely for females[৩০] and 1.5–2.5 times more likely for males.[৩১][৩২] The higher figures reach 4.6 times more likely in females[৩৩] and 14.6 times more likely in males.[১৩]

Race and age play a factor in the increased risk. The highest ratios for males are attributed to young Caucasians. By the age of 25, their risk is more than halved; however, the risk for black gay males at that age steadily increases to 8.6 times more likely. Over a lifetime, the increased likelihoods are 5.7 times for white and 12.8 for black gay and bisexual males. Lesbian and bisexual females have the opposite trend, with fewer attempts during the teenager years compared to heterosexual females. Through a lifetime, the likelihood for Caucasian females is nearly triple that of their heterosexual counterparts; however, for black females there is minimal change (less than 0.1 to 0.3 difference), with heterosexual black females having a slightly higher risk throughout most of the age-based study.[১৩]

Gay and lesbian youth who attempt suicide are disproportionately subject to anti-gay attitudes, often have fewer skills for coping with discrimination, isolation, and loneliness,[১৩][৩৪] and were more likely to experience family rejection[৩৫] than those who do not attempt suicide. Another study found that gay and bisexual youth who attempted suicide had more feminine gender roles,[৩৬] adopted a non-heterosexual identity at a young age and were more likely than peers to report sexual abuse, drug abuse, and arrests for misconduct.[৩৬] One study found that same-sex sexual behavior, but not homosexual attraction or homosexual identity, was significantly predictive of suicide among Norwegian adolescents.[৩৭]

Sexual orientation identity development

  • Coming out: Many gay, lesbian and bisexual people go through a "coming out" experience at some point in their lives. Psychologists often say this process includes several stages "in which there is an awareness of being different from peers ('sensitization'), and in which people start to question their sexual identity ('identity confusion'). Subsequently, they start to explore practically the option of being gay, lesbian or bisexual and learn to deal with the stigma ('identity assumption'). In the final stage, they integrate their sexual desires into a position understanding of self ('commitment')."[১৩] However, the process is not always linear[৩৮] and it may differ for lesbians, gay men and bisexual individuals.[৩৯]
  • Different degrees of coming out: One study found that gay men are more likely to be out to friends and siblings than to co-workers, parents, and more distant relatives.[৪০]
  • Coming out and well-being: Same-sex couples who are openly gay are more satisfied in their relationships.[৪১] For women who self-identify as lesbian, the more people know about her sexual orientation, the less anxiety, more positive affectivity, and greater self-esteem she has.[৪২]
  • Rejection of gay identity: Various studies report that for some religious people, rejecting a gay identity appears to relieve the distress caused by conflicts between religious values and sexual orientation.[২৫][৪৩][৪৪][৪৫][৪৬] After reviewing the research, Judith Glassgold, chair of the American Psychological Association sexuality task force, said some people are content in denying a gay identity and "there is no clear evidence of harm".[৪৭]

Fluidity of sexual orientation

The American Psychiatric Association (APA) states that "some people believe that sexual orientation is innate and fixed; however, sexual orientation develops across a person’s lifetime".[৪৮] In a statement issued jointly with other major American medical organizations, the American Psychological Association states that "different people realize at different points in their lives that they are heterosexual, gay, lesbian, or bisexual".[৪৯] A report from the Centre for Addiction and Mental Health states that, "For some people, sexual orientation is continuous and fixed throughout their lives. For others, sexual orientation may be fluid and change over time".[৫০] Lisa Diamond's study "Female bisexuality from adolescence to adulthood" suggests that there is "considerable fluidity in bisexual, unlabeled, and lesbian women's attractions, behaviors, and identities".[৫১][৫২]

Parenting

LGBT parenting is when lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender (LGBT) people are parents to one or more children, either as biological or non-biological parents. Gay men have options which include "foster care, variations of domestic and international adoption, diverse forms of surrogacy (whether "traditional" or gestational), and kinship arrangements, wherein they might coparent with a woman or women with whom they are intimately but not sexually involved."[৫৩][৫৪][৫৫][৫৬][৫৭] LGBT parents can also include single parents; to a lesser extent, the term sometimes refers to parents of LGBT children.

In the 2000 U.S. Census, 33 percent of female same-sex couple households and 22 percent of male same-sex couple households reported at least one child under eighteen living in their home.[৫৮] Some children do not know they have an LGBT parent; coming out issues vary and some parents may never come out to their children.[৫৯][৬০] adoption by LGBT couples and LGBT parenting in general may be controversial in some countries. In January 2008, the European Court of Human Rights ruled that same-sex couples have the right to adopt a child.[৬১][৬২] In the U.S., LGB people can legally adopt, as individuals, in all fifty states.[৬৩]

Although it is sometimes asserted in policy debates that heterosexual couples are inherently better parents than same-sex couples, or that the children of lesbian or gay parents fare worse than children raised by heterosexual parents, those assertions are not supported by scientific research literature.[৬৪][৬৫] There is ample evidence to show that children raised by same-gender parents fare as well as those raised by heterosexual parents. Much research has documented the lack of correlation between parents' sexual orientation and any measure of a child's emotional, psychosocial, and behavioral adjustment. These data have demonstrated no risk to children as a result of growing up in a family with one or more gay parents.[৬৬] No research supports the widely held conviction that the gender of parents influences the well-being of the child.[৬৭] If gay, lesbian, or bisexual parents were inherently less capable than otherwise comparable heterosexual parents, their children would present more poorly regardless of the type of sample. This pattern has not been observed. Given the consistent failures in this research literature to disprove the null hypothesis, the burden of empirical proof is on those who argue that the children of sexual minority parents are worse off than the children of heterosexual parents.[৬৮]

Professor Judith Stacey, of New York University, stated: “Rarely is there as much consensus in any area of social science as in the case of gay parenting, which is why the American Academy of Pediatrics and all of the major professional organizations with expertise in child welfare have issued reports and resolutions in support of gay and lesbian parental rights”.[৬৯] These organizations include the American Academy of Pediatrics,[৬৬] the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry,[৭০] the American Psychiatric Association,[৭১] the American Psychological Association,[৭২] the American Psychoanalytic Association,[৭৩] the National Association of Social Workers,[৬৪] the Child Welfare League of America,[৭৪] the North American Council on Adoptable Children,[৭৫] and Canadian Psychological Association (CPA). CPA is concerned that some persons and institutions are misinterpreting the findings of psychological research to support their positions, when their positions are more accurately based on other systems of belief or values.[৭৬]

The vast majority of families in the United States today are not the "middle-class family with a bread-winning father and a stay-at-home mother, married to each other and raising their biological children" that has been viewed as the norm. Since the end of the 1980s, it has been well established that children and adolescents can adjust just as well in nontraditional settings as in traditional settings.[৭৭]

Psychotherapy

Most people with a homosexual orientation who seek psychotherapy do so for the same reasons as straight people (stress, relationship difficulties, difficulty adjusting to social or work situations, etc.); their sexual orientation may be of primary, incidental, or no importance to their issues and treatment. Regardless of the issue that psychotherapy is sought for, there is a high risk of anti-gay bias being directed at non-heterosexual clients.[১৫]

Relationship counseling

Most relationship issues are shared equally among couples regardless of sexual orientation, but LGBT clients additionally have to deal with homophobia, heterosexism, and other societal oppressions. Individuals may also be at different stages in the coming out process. Often, same-sex couples do not have as many role models for successful relationships as opposite-sex couples. There may be issues with gender-role socialization that does not affect opposite-sex couples.[৭৮]

A significant number of men and women experience conflict surrounding homosexual expression within a mixed-orientation marriage.[৭৯] Therapy may include helping the client feel more comfortable and accepting of same-sex feelings and to explore ways of incorporating same-sex and opposite-sex feelings into life patterns.[৮০] Although a strong homosexual identity was associated with difficulties in marital satisfaction, viewing the same-sex activities as compulsive facilitated commitment to the marriage and to monogamy.[৮১]

Gay affirmative psychotherapy

Gay affirmative psychotherapy is a form of psychotherapy for gay and lesbian clients which encourages them to accept their sexual orientation, and does not attempt to change their sexual orientation to heterosexual, or to eliminate or diminish their same-sex desires and behaviors. The American Psychological Association (APA) and the British Psychological Society offer guidelines and materials for gay affirmative psychotherapy.[৮২][৮৩] Practitioners of gay affirmative psychotherapy states that homosexuality or bisexuality is not a mental illness, and that embracing and affirming gay identity can be a key component to recovery from other mental illnesses or substance abuse.[৮২] Some people may find neither gay affirmative therapy nor conversion therapy appropriate, however. Clients whose religious beliefs are inconsistent with homosexual behavior may require some other method of integrating their conflicting religious and sexual selves.[৮৪]

Sexual orientation identity exploration

The APA recommends that if a client wants treatment to change his sexual orientation, the therapist should explore the reasons behind the desire, without favoring any particular outcome. The therapist should neither promote nor reject the idea of celibacy, but help the client come to their own decisions by evaluating the reasons behind the patient's goals.[৮৫] One example of sexual orientation identity exploration is Sexual Identity Therapy.[২৫]

After exploration, a patient may proceed with sexual orientation identity reconstruction, which helps a patient reconstruct sexual orientation identity. Psychotherapy, support groups, and life events can influence identity development; similarly, self-awareness, self-conception, and identity may evolve during treatment.[২৫] It can change sexual orientation identity (private and public identification, and group belonging), emotional adjustment (self-stigma and shame reduction), and personal beliefs, values and norms (change of religious and moral belief, behavior and motivation).[২৫] Some therapies include Gender Wholeness Therapy.[৮৬]

The American Psychiatric Association states in their official statement release on the matter: "The potential risks of 'reparative therapy' are great and include depression, anxiety, and self-destructive behavior, since therapist alignment with societal prejudices against homosexuality may reinforce self-hatred already experienced by the patient. Many patients who have undergone 'reparative therapy' relate that they were inaccurately told that homosexuals are lonely, unhappy individuals who never achieve acceptance or satisfaction. The possibility that the person might achieve happiness and satisfying interpersonal relationships as a gay man or lesbian are not presented, nor are alternative approaches to dealing with the effects of societal stigmatization discussed. APA recognizes that in the course of ongoing psychiatric treatment, there may be appropriate clinical indications for attempting to change sexual behaviors."[৮৭]

The American Psychological Association aligns with this in a Resolution: it "urges all mental health professionals to take the lead in removing the stigma of mental illness that has long been associated with homosexual orientation" (Conger, 1975, p. 633); and "Therefore be it further resolved that the American Psychological Association opposes portrayals of lesbian, gay, and bisexual youth and adults as mentally ill due to their sexual orientation and supports the dissemination of accurate information about sexual orientation, and mental health, and appropriate interventions in order to counteract bias that is based in ignorance or unfounded beliefs about sexual orientation."[৮৮]

The American College of Pediatrics advises people struggling with their sexuality: "You are normal. Homosexuality is not a mental disorder. All of the major medical organizations, including The American Psychiatric Association, The American Psychological Association, and the American Academy of Pediatrics agree that homosexuality is not an illness or disorder, but a form of sexual expression. No one knows what causes a person to be gay, bisexual, or straight. There probably are a number of factors. Some may be biological. Others may be psychological. The reasons can vary from one person to another. The fact is, you do not choose to be gay, bisexual, or straight."[৮৯]

Developments in individual psychology

In contemporary Adlerian thought, homosexuals are not considered within the problematic discourse of the "failures of life". Christopher Shelley (1998), an Adlerian psychotherapist, published a volume of essays in the 1990s[তথ্যসূত্র প্রয়োজন] that feature Freudian, (post)Jungian and Adlerian contributions that demonstrate affirmative shifts in the depth psychologies. These shifts show how depth psychology can be utilized to support rather than pathologize gay and lesbian psychotherapy clients. The Journal of Individual Psychology, the English language flagship publication of Adlerian Psychology, released a volume in the summer of 2008 that reviews and corrects Adler's previously held beliefs on the homosexual community.

See also

References

  1. Katz, J (১৯৯৫)। Gay and American History: Lesbians and Gay men in the United States। New York: Thomas Crowell। 
  2. Glassgold, Judith। "Report of the American Psychological Association Task Force: Appropriate Therapeutic Responses to Sexual Orientation" (পিডিএফ)। সংগ্রহের তারিখ 10/12/2013  এখানে তারিখের মান পরীক্ষা করুন: |সংগ্রহের-তারিখ= (সাহায্য)
  3. Freud, Sigmund (১৯৫৩)। Three essays on the theory of sexuality। London: Hogarth Press। 
  4. Ruitenbeek, H.M. (১৯৬৩)। The problem of Homosexuality in modern society। New York: Dutton। 
  5. Rubinstien, Gigi (জানুয়ারি ৬, ২০১০)। "Narcissism and self esteem among homosexual and heterosexual male students" (PDF)Journal of Sex & Marital Therapy36: 1, 24–34। ডিওআই:10.1080/0092630920-337-5594। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ফেব্রুয়ারি ১৬, ২০১৭ 
  6. Weideman, G. (১৯৬২)। "Survey of Psychoanalytic literature on overt homosexuality"। Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association10: 286–409। 
  7. Freud, Sigmund (১৯৫১)। "Letter to an American Mother"। American Journal of Psychiatry107: 787। 
  8. Spencer, Colin (১৯৯৫)। Homosexuality in History। New York: Harcourt Brace & Company। 
  9. Ellis, Havelock (১৯৬৩)। If this be sexual heresy...। New York: Lyle Stuart Inc। 
  10. Ellis, Havelock (১৯৪৬)। Psychology of Sex। New York: Emerson Books। 
  11. Geddes, Donald Porter (১৯৫৪)। An analysis of the Kinsey reports on sexual behavior in the human male and female। New York: Dutton। 
  12. LeVay, Simon (1996). Queer Science: The Use and Abuse of Research into Homosexuality. Cambridge: The MIT Press আইএসবিএন ০-২৬২-১২১৯৯-৯[পৃষ্ঠা নম্বর প্রয়োজন]
  13. উদ্ধৃতি ত্রুটি: <ref> ট্যাগ বৈধ নয়; intro নামের সূত্রটির জন্য কোন লেখা প্রদান করা হয়নি
  14. National Affirmation Annual Conference: "Homosexuality: A Psychiatrist's Response to LDS Social Services", September 5, 1999
  15. Cabaj, R; Stein, T. eds. Textbook of Homosexuality and Mental Health, p. 421
  16. Herek, et al. (1997)
  17. Holtzen and Agresti (1990).
  18. Newman and Muzzonigro (1993)
  19. উদ্ধৃতি ত্রুটি: <ref> ট্যাগ বৈধ নয়; Etengoff, C. 2014 নামের সূত্রটির জন্য কোন লেখা প্রদান করা হয়নি
  20. Sandfort, et al. (1999)
  21. Brand, et al. (1992).
  22. Siever (1994).
  23. Hiatt and Hargrave (1994).
  24. Finlay and Scheltema (1991)
  25. Appropriate Therapeutic Responses to Sexual Orientation
  26. Westefeld, John; Maples, Michael; Buford, Brian; Taylor, Steve (২০০১)। "Gay, Lesbian, and Bisexual College Students"। Journal of College Student Psychotherapy15 (3): 71–82। ডিওআই:10.1300/J035v15n03_06 
  27. Fergusson DM, Horwood LJ, Ridder EM, Beautrais AL (জুলাই ২০০৫)। "Sexual orientation and mental health in a birth cohort of young adults"। Psychological Medicine35 (7): 971–81। ডিওআই:10.1017/S0033291704004222পিএমআইডি 16045064 
  28. Silenzio VM, Pena JB, Duberstein PR, Cerel J, Knox KL (নভেম্বর ২০০৭)। "Sexual Orientation and Risk Factors for Suicidal Ideation and Suicide Attempts Among Adolescents and Young Adults"American Journal of Public Health97 (11): 2017–9। ডিওআই:10.2105/AJPH.2006.095943পিএমআইডি 17901445পিএমসি 2040383অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  29. Gay, Lesbian, Bisexual & Transgender "Attempted Suicide" Incidences/Risks Suicidality Studies From 1970 to 2009
  30. Bell & Weinberg (1978): Tables 21.14 & 21.15, pages 453–454.
  31. Safren SA, Heimberg RG (ডিসেম্বর ১৯৯৯)। "Depression, hopelessness, suicidality, and related factors in sexual minority and heterosexual adolescents"। Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology67 (6): 859–66। ডিওআই:10.1037/0022-006X.67.6.859পিএমআইডি 10596508 
  32. Russell ST, Joyner K (আগস্ট ২০০১)। "Adolescent Sexual Orientation and Suicide Risk: Evidence From a National Study"American Journal of Public Health91 (8): 1276–81। ডিওআই:10.2105/AJPH.91.8.1276পিএমআইডি 11499118পিএমসি 1446760অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  33. Saghir MT, Robins E, Walbran B, Gentry KA (আগস্ট ১৯৭০)। "Homosexuality. IV. Psychiatric disorders and disability in the female homosexual"The American Journal of Psychiatry127 (2): 147–54। ডিওআই:10.1176/ajp.127.2.147পিএমআইডি 5473144 
  34. Rotheram-Boris, et al. (1994); Proctor and Groze (1994)
  35. Ryan C, Huebner D, Diaz RM, Sanchez J (জানুয়ারি ২০০৯)। "Family rejection as a predictor of negative health outcomes in white and Latino lesbian, gay, and bisexual young adults"। Pediatrics123 (1): 346–52। ডিওআই:10.1542/peds.2007-3524পিএমআইডি 19117902 
  36. Remafedi G, Farrow JA, Deisher RW (জুন ১৯৯১)। "Risk factors for attempted suicide in gay and bisexual youth"Pediatrics87 (6): 869–75। পিএমআইডি 2034492 
  37. Wichstrøm L, Hegna K (ফেব্রুয়ারি ২০০৩)। "Sexual orientation and suicide attempt: a longitudinal study of the general Norwegian adolescent population"। Journal of Abnormal Psychology112 (1): 144–51। ডিওআই:10.1037/0021-843X.112.1.144পিএমআইডি 12653422 
  38. Rust (1993)
  39. Monteflores and Schultz (1978).
  40. Berger (1992)
  41. Berger RM (জুলাই ১৯৯০)। "Passing: impact on the quality of same-sex couple relationships"। Social Work35 (4): 328–32। পিএমআইডি 2392712 
  42. Jordan KM, Deluty RH (১৯৯৮)। "Coming out for lesbian women: its relation to anxiety, positive affectivity, self-esteem, and social support"। Journal of Homosexuality35 (2): 41–63। ডিওআই:10.1300/J082v35n02_03পিএমআইডি 9524921 
  43. Ponticelli C. M. (১৯৯৯)। "Crafting stories of sexual identity reconstruction"। Social Psychology Quarterly62: 157–172। ডিওআই:10.2307/2695855 
  44. Erzen, T. (2006). Straight to Jesus: Sexual and Christian conversions in the ex-gay movement. Los Angeles: University of California Press.
  45. Thumma S (১৯৯১)। "Negotiating a religious identity: The case of the gay evangelical"। Sociological Analysis52: 333–347। ডিওআই:10.2307/3710850 
  46. Kerr, R. A. (1997). The experience of integrating gay identity with evangelical Christian faith" Dissertation Abstracts International 58(09), 5124B. (UMI No. 9810055).
  47. A New Therapy on Faith and Sexual Identity: Psychological Association Revises Treatment Guidelines to Allow Counselors to Help Clients Reject Their Same-Sex Attractions
  48. American Psychiatric Association (মে ২০০০)। "Gay, Lesbian and Bisexual Issues"। Association of Gay and Lesbian Psychiatrics। 
  49. "Just the Facts About Sexual Orientation & Youth: A Primer for Principals, Educators and School Personnel"American Academy of Pediatrics, American Counseling Association, American Association of School Administrators, American Federation of Teachers, American Psychological Association, American School Health Association, The Interfaith Alliance, National Association of School Psychologists, National Association of Social Workers, National Education Association। ১৯৯৯। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০০৭-০৮-২৮ 
  50. "ARQ2: Question A2 – Sexual Orientation"। Centre for Addiction and Mental Health। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০০৭-০৮-২৮ 
  51. Diamond, Lisa M. (জানুয়ারি ২০০৮)। "Female bisexuality from adolescence to adulthood: Results from a 10-year longitudinal study" (PDF)Developmental Psychology44 (1): 5–14। ডিওআই:10.1037/0012-1649.44.1.5পিএমআইডি 18194000 
  52. "Bisexual women – new research findings"। Women's Health News। জানুয়ারি ১৭, ২০০৮। 
  53. Berkowitz, D & Marsiglio, W (2007). Gay Men: Negotiating Procreative, Father, and Family Identities. Journal of Marriage and Family 69 (May 2007): 366–381
  54. Butler, Katy (মার্চ ৭, ২০০৬)। "Many Couples Must Negotiate Terms of 'Brokeback' Marriages"। New York Times। 
  55. The Married Lesbian
  56. Büntzly G (১৯৯৩)। "Gay fathers in straight marriages"। J Homosex24 (3–4): 107–14। ডিওআই:10.1300/J082v24n03_07পিএমআইডি 8505530 
  57. Bozett, Frederick W. (১৯৮৭-০৮-১৯)। "The Heterosexually Married Gay and Lesbian Parent"। Gay and Lesbian Parents। পৃষ্ঠা 138। আইএসবিএন 0-275-92541-2 
  58. APA Policy Statement on Sexual Orientation, Parents & Children, American Psychological Association, July 28 & 30, 2004. Retrieved on 2007-04-06.
  59. Dunne EJ (১৯৮৭)। "Helping gay fathers come out to their children"। J Homosex14 (1–2): 213–22। ডিওআই:10.1300/J082v14n01_16পিএমআইডি 3655343 
  60. A Family Matter: When a Spouse Comes Out as Gay, Lesbian, or Bisexual
  61. EMRK is for the LGBT adoption [অকার্যকর সংযোগ]
  62. Euronews: Gleichgeschlechtliche Adoptiveltern – Gerichtshof rügt Frankreich (german)
  63. "Adoption Laws: State by State"। Human Rights Campaign। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০০৮-০৭-০৯ 
  64. Case No. S147999 in the Supreme Court of the State of California, In re Marriage Cases Judicial Council Coordination Proceeding No. 4365, Application for leave to file brief amici curiae in support of the parties challenging the marriage exclusion, and brief amici curiae of the American Psychological Association, California Psychological Association, American Psychiatric Association, National Association of Social Workers, and National Association of Social Workers, California Chapter in support of the parties challenging the marriage exclusion
  65. Canadian Psychological Association: Brief presented to the Legislative House of Commons Committee on Bill C38 By the Canadian Psychological Association June 2, 2005.
  66. Pawelski JG, Perrin EC, Foy JM, ও অন্যান্য (জুলাই ২০০৬)। "The effects of marriage, civil union, and domestic partnership laws on the health and well-being of children"। Pediatrics118 (1): 349–64। ডিওআই:10.1542/peds.2006-1279পিএমআইডি 16818585 
  67. (How) Does the Sexual Orientation of Parent's Matter?
  68. Herek GM (সেপ্টেম্বর ২০০৬)। "Legal recognition of same-sex relationships in the United States: a social science perspective" (পিডিএফ)The American Psychologist61 (6): 607–21। ডিওআই:10.1037/0003-066X.61.6.607পিএমআইডি 16953748। ২০১০-০৬-১০ তারিখে মূল (পিডিএফ) থেকে আর্কাইভ করা। 
  69. cited in Cooper & Cates, 2006, p. 36; citation available on http://www.psychology.org.au/Assets/Files/LGBT-Families-Lit-Review.pdf
  70. Children with Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual and Transgender Parents
  71. Adoption and Co-parenting of Children by Same-sex Couples
  72. Sexual Orientation, Parents, & Children
  73. Position Statement on Gay and Lesbian Parenting ওয়েব্যাক মেশিনে আর্কাইভকৃত ২০১১-০৯-২৮ তারিখে
  74. Position Statement on Parenting of Children by Lesbian, Gay, and Bisexual Adults ওয়েব্যাক মেশিনে আর্কাইভকৃত ২০১০-০৬-১৩ তারিখে
  75. NACAC Position Statements
  76. Marriage of Same-Sex Couples – 2006 Position Statement Canadian Psychological Association
  77. Michael Lamb, Ph.D.: Affidavit – United States District Court for the District of Massachusetts (2009)[স্থায়ীভাবে অকার্যকর সংযোগ]
  78. Relationship therapy with same-sex couples
  79. Wolf TJ (১৯৮৭)। "Group psychotherapy for bisexual men and their wives"। J Homosex.14 (1–2): 191–9। ডিওআই:10.1300/J082v14n01_14পিএমআইডি 3655341 
  80. Coleman E (১৯৮১)। "Bisexual and gay men in heterosexual marriage: conflicts and resolutions in therapy"। J Homosex.7 (2–3): 93–103। ডিওআই:10.1300/J082v07n02_11পিএমআইডি 7346553 
  81. Schneider JP, Schneider BH (১৯৯০)। "Marital satisfaction during recovery from self-identified sexual addiction among bisexual men and their wives"। J Sex Marital Ther.16 (4): 230–50। ডিওআই:10.1080/00926239008405460পিএমআইডি 2079706 
  82. APA:Guidelines for Psychotherapy with Lesbian, Gay, & Bisexual Clients
  83. British Psychological Society। "Guidelines and Literature Review for Psychologists Working Therapeutically with Sexual and Gender Minority Clients" (পিডিএফ)British Psychological Society 
  84. Haldeman, Douglas (২০০৪)। "When Sexual and Religious Orientation Collide:Considerations in Working with Conflicted Same-Sex Attracted Male Clients"The Counseling Psychologist। The Counseling Psychologist। 32 (5): 691–715। ডিওআই:10.1177/0011000004267560 
  85. American Psychological Association: Resolution on Appropriate Affirmative Responses to Sexual Orientation Distress and Change Efforts
  86. Luo, Michael (২০০৭-০২-১২)। "Some Tormented by Homosexuality Look to a Controversial Therapy"। The New York Times। পৃষ্ঠা 1। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০০৭-০৮-২৮ 
  87. "Psychiatric Treatment and Sexual Orientation POSITION STATEMENT"Psychiatric Treatment and Sexual Orientation POSITION STATEMENT। American Psychiatric Association। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ১২ অক্টোবর ২০১১ 
  88. "Resolution on Appropriate Therapeutic Responses to Sexual Orientation"Resolution on Appropriate Therapeutic Responses to Sexual Orientation। American Psychological Association। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ১২ অক্টোবর ২০১১ 
  89. "Gay, Lesbian, and Bisexual Teens: Facts for Teens and Their Parents"Healthy ChildrenAmerican Academy of Pediatrics। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০ ডিসেম্বর ২০১৬ 

Resources and external links

American Psychological Association
American Academy of Pediatrics

British Psychological Society

National Mental Health Association

Join statements by professional bodies in the United Kingdom

Irreducible complexity (IC) is the argument that certain biological systems cannot evolve by successive small modifications to pre-existing functional systems through natural selection. Irreducible complexity is central to the creationist concept of intelligent design, but it is rejected by the scientific community,[১] which regards intelligent design as pseudoscience.[২] Irreducible complexity is one of two main arguments used by intelligent design proponents, the other being specified complexity.[৩]

The theological argument from design was presented in creation science with assertions that evolution could not explain complex molecular mechanisms, and in 1993 Michael Behe, a professor of biochemistry at Lehigh University, presented these arguments in a revised version of Of Pandas and People.[৪] In his 1996 book Darwin's Black Box he called this irreducible complexity and said it made evolution through natural selection of random mutations impossible.[৫] This was based on the mistaken assumption that evolution relies on improvement of existing functions, ignoring how complex adaptations originate from changes in function, and disregarded published research.[৪] Evolutionary biologists have published rebuttals showing how systems discussed by Behe can evolve,[৬][৭] and examples documented through comparative genomics show that complex molecular systems are formed by the addition of components as revealed by different temporal origins of their proteins.[৮][৯]

In the 2005 Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District trial, Behe gave testimony on the subject of irreducible complexity. The court found that "Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity has been refuted in peer-reviewed research papers and has been rejected by the scientific community at large."[১]

Definitions

Michael Behe defined irreducible complexity in natural selection in his book Darwin's Black Box:

... a single system which is composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, and where the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning.[১০]

A second definition given by Behe (his "evolutionary definition") is as follows:

An irreducibly complex evolutionary pathway is one that contains one or more unselected steps (that is, one or more necessary-but-unselected mutations). The degree of irreducible complexity is the number of unselected steps in the pathway.[১১]

Intelligent design advocate William A. Dembski gives this definition:

A system performing a given basic function is irreducibly complex if it includes a set of well-matched, mutually interacting, nonarbitrarily individuated parts such that each part in the set is indispensable to maintaining the system's basic, and therefore original, function. The set of these indispensable parts is known as the irreducible core of the system.[১২]

History

Forerunners

The argument from irreducible complexity is a descendant of the teleological argument for God (the argument from design or from complexity). This states that because certain things in nature appear very complicated, they must have been designed. William Paley famously argued, in his 1802 watchmaker analogy, that complexity in nature implies a God for the same reason that the existence of a watch implies the existence of a watchmaker.[১৩] This argument has a long history, and one can trace it back at least as far as Cicero's De Natura Deorum ii.34,[১৪][১৫] written in 45 BC.

Up to the 18th century

Galen (1st and 2nd centuries AD) wrote about the large number of parts of the body and their relationships, which observation was cited as evidence for creation.[১৬] The idea that the interdependence between parts would have implications for the origins of living things was raised by writers starting with Pierre Gassendi in the mid-17th century[১৭] and by John Wilkins (1614-1672), who wrote (citing Galen), "Now to imagine, that all these things, according to their several kinds, could be brought into this regular frame and order, to which such an infinite number of Intentions are required, without the contrivance of some wise Agent, must needs be irrational in the highest degree."[১৮] In the late 17th-century, Thomas Burnet referred to "a multitude of pieces aptly joyn'd" to argue against the eternity of life.[১৯] In the early 18th century, Nicolas Malebranche[২০] wrote "An organized body contains an infinity of parts that mutually depend upon one another in relation to particular ends, all of which must be actually formed in order to work as a whole", arguing in favor of preformation, rather than epigenesis, of the individual;[২১] and a similar argument about the origins of the individual was made by other 18th-century students of natural history.[২২] In his 1790 book, The Critique of Judgment, Kant is said by Guyer to argue that "we cannot conceive how a whole that comes into being only gradually from its parts can nevertheless be the cause of the properties of those parts".[২৩]

19th century

Chapter XV of Paley's Natural Theology discusses at length what he called "relations" of parts of living things as an indication of their design.[১৩]

Georges Cuvier applied his principle of the correlation of parts to describe an animal from fragmentary remains. For Cuvier, this related to another principle of his, the conditions of existence, which excluded the possibility of transmutation of species.[২৪]

While he did not originate the term, Charles Darwin identified the argument as a possible way to falsify a prediction of the theory of evolution at the outset. In The Origin of Species (1859), he wrote, "If it could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed, which could not possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modifications, my theory would absolutely break down. But I can find out no such case."[২৫] Darwin's theory of evolution challenges the teleological argument by postulating an alternative explanation to that of an intelligent designer—namely, evolution by natural selection. By showing how simple unintelligent forces can ratchet up designs of extraordinary complexity without invoking outside design, Darwin showed that an intelligent designer was not the necessary conclusion to draw from complexity in nature. The argument from irreducible complexity attempts to demonstrate that certain biological features cannot be purely the product of Darwinian evolution.[২৬]

In the late 19th century, in a dispute between supporters of the adequacy of natural selection and those who held for inheritance of acquired characteristics, one of the arguments made repeatedly by Herbert Spencer, and followed by others, depended on what Spencer referred to as co-adaptation of co-operative parts, as in:

"We come now to Professor Weismann's endeavour to disprove my second thesis — that it is impossible to explain by natural selection alone the co-adaptation of co-operative parts. It is thirty years since this was set forth in "The Principles of Biology." In §166, I instanced the enormous horns of the extinct Irish elk, and contended that in this and in kindred cases, where for the efficient use of some one enlarged part many other parts have to be simultaneously enlarged, it is out of the question to suppose that they can have all spontaneously varied in the required proportions."[২৭][২৮]

Darwin responded to Spencer's objections in chapter XXV of The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication (1868).[২৯] The history of this concept in the dispute has been characterized: "An older and more religious tradition of idealist thinkers were committed to the explanation of complex adaptive contrivances by intelligent design. ... Another line of thinkers, unified by the recurrent publications of Herbert Spencer, also saw co-adaptation as a composed, irreducible whole, but sought to explain it by the inheritance of acquired characteristics."[৩০]

St. George Jackson Mivart raised the objection to natural selection that "Complex and simultaneous co-ordinations … until so far developed as to effect the requisite junctions, are useless"[৩১] which "amounts to the concept of "irreducible complexity" as defined by … Michael Behe".[৩২]

20th century

Hermann Muller, in the early 20th century, discussed a concept similar to irreducible complexity. However, far from seeing this as a problem for evolution, he described the "interlocking" of biological features as a consequence to be expected of evolution, which would lead to irreversibility of some evolutionary changes.[৩৩] He wrote, "Being thus finally woven, as it were, into the most intimate fabric of the organism, the once novel character can no longer be withdrawn with impunity, and may have become vitally necessary."[৩৪]

In 1974 the young Earth creationist Henry M. Morris introduced a similar concept in his book Scientific Creationism, in which he wrote; "This issue can actually be attacked quantitatively, using simple principles of mathematical probability. The problem is simply whether a complex system, in which many components function unitedly together, and in which each component is uniquely necessary to the efficient functioning of the whole, could ever arise by random processes."[৩৫]

In 1975 Thomas H. Frazzetta published a book-length study of a concept similar to irreducible complexity, explained by gradual, step-wise, non-teleological evolution. Frazzetta wrote:

"A complex adaptation is one constructed of several components that must blend together operationally to make the adaptation "work". It is analogous to a machine whose performance depends upon careful cooperation among its parts. In the case of the machine, no single part can greatly be altered without changing the performance of the entire machine."

The machine that he chose as an analog is the Peaucellier–Lipkin linkage, and one biological system given extended description was the jaw apparatus of a python. The conclusion of this investigation, rather than that evolution of a complex adaptation was impossible, "awed by the adaptations of living things, to be stunned by their complexity and suitability", was "to accept the inescapable but not humiliating fact that much of mankind can be seen in a tree or a lizard."[৩৬]

In 1981, Ariel Roth, in defense of the creation-science position in the trial McLean v. Arkansas, said of "complex integrated structures": "This system would not be functional until all the parts were there ... How did these parts survive during evolution ...?"[৩৭]

In 1985 Cairns-Smith wrote of "interlocking": "How can a complex collaboration between components evolve in small steps?" and used the analogy of the scaffolding called centering - used to build an arch then removed afterwards: "Surely there was 'scaffolding'. Before the multitudinous components of present biochemistry could come to lean together they had to lean on something else."[৩৮][৩৯] However, neither Muller or Cairns-Smith claimed their ideas as evidence of something supernatural.[৪০]

An essay in support of creationism published in 1994 referred to bacterial flagella as showing "multiple, integrated components", where "nothing about them works unless every one of their complexly fashioned and integrated components are in place". The author asked the reader to "imagine the effects of natural selection on those organisms that fortuitously evolved the flagella ... without the concommitant [সিক] control mechanisms".[৪১][৪]

An early concept of irreducibly complex systems comes from Ludwig von Bertalanffy (1901-1972), an Austrian biologist.[৪২] He believed that complex systems must be examined as complete, irreducible systems in order to fully understand how they work. He extended his work on biological complexity into a general theory of systems in a book titled General Systems Theory.

After James Watson and Francis Crick published the structure of DNA in the early 1950s, General Systems Theory lost many of its adherents in the physical and biological sciences.[৪৩] However, Systems theory remained popular in the social sciences long after its demise in the physical and biological sciences.

Origins

চিত্র:Darwinsblackbox.jpg
Michael Behe's controversial book Darwin's Black Box popularized the concept of irreducible complexity.

Michael Behe developed his ideas on the concept around 1992, in the early days of the 'wedge movement', and first presented his ideas about "irreducible complexity" in June 1993 when the "Johnson-Behe cadre of scholars" met at Pajaro Dunes in California.[৪৪] He set out his ideas in the second edition of Of Pandas and People published in 1993, extensively revising Chapter 6 Biochemical Similarities with new sections on the complex mechanism of blood clotting and on the origin of proteins.[৪৫]

He first used the term "irreducible complexity" in his 1996 book Darwin's Black Box, to refer to certain complex biochemical cellular systems. He posits that evolutionary mechanisms cannot explain the development of such "irreducibly complex" systems. Notably, Behe credits philosopher William Paley for the original concept (alone among the predecessors) and suggests that his application of the concept to biological systems is entirely original.

Intelligent design advocates argue that irreducibly complex systems must have been deliberately engineered by some form of intelligence.

In 2001, Michael Behe wrote: "[T]here is an asymmetry between my current definition of irreducible complexity and the task facing natural selection. I hope to repair this defect in future work." Behe specifically explained that the "current definition puts the focus on removing a part from an already functioning system", but the "difficult task facing Darwinian evolution, however, would not be to remove parts from sophisticated pre-existing systems; it would be to bring together components to make a new system in the first place".[৪৬] In the 2005 Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District trial, Behe testified under oath that he "did not judge [the asymmetry] serious enough to [have revised the book] yet."[৪৭]

Behe additionally testified that the presence of irreducible complexity in organisms would not rule out the involvement of evolutionary mechanisms in the development of organic life. He further testified that he knew of no earlier "peer reviewed articles in scientific journals discussing the intelligent design of the blood clotting cascade," but that there were "probably a large number of peer reviewed articles in science journals that demonstrate that the blood clotting system is indeed a purposeful arrangement of parts of great complexity and sophistication."[৪৮] (The judge ruled that "intelligent design is not science and is essentially religious in nature".)[৪৯]

According to the theory of evolution, genetic variations occur without specific design or intent. The environment "selects" the variants that have the highest fitness, which are then passed on to the next generation of organisms. Change occurs by the gradual operation of natural forces over time, perhaps slowly, perhaps more quickly (see punctuated equilibrium). This process is able to adapt complex structures from simpler beginnings, or convert complex structures from one function to another (see spandrel). Most intelligent design advocates accept that evolution occurs through mutation and natural selection at the "micro level", such as changing the relative frequency of various beak lengths in finches, but assert that it cannot account for irreducible complexity, because none of the parts of an irreducible system would be functional or advantageous until the entire system is in place.

The mousetrap example

Michael Behe believes that many aspects of life show evidence of design, using the mousetrap in an analogy disputed by others.[৫০]

Behe uses the mousetrap as an illustrative example of this concept. A mousetrap consists of five interacting pieces: the base, the catch, the spring, the hammer, and the hold-down bar. All of these must be in place for the mousetrap to work, as the removal of any one piece destroys the function of the mousetrap. Likewise, he asserts that biological systems require multiple parts working together in order to function. Intelligent design advocates claim that natural selection could not create from scratch those systems for which science is currently unable to find a viable evolutionary pathway of successive, slight modifications, because the selectable function is only present when all parts are assembled.

In his 2008 book Only A Theory, biologist Kenneth R. Miller challenges Behe's claim that the mousetrap is irreducibly complex.[৫১] Miller observes that various subsets of the five components can be devised to form cooperative units, ones that have different functions from the mousetrap and so, in biological terms, could form functional spandrels before being adapted to the new function of catching mice. In an example taken from his high school experience, Miller recalls that one of his classmates

...struck upon the brilliant idea of using an old, broken mousetrap as a spitball catapult, and it worked brilliantly.... It had worked perfectly as something other than a mousetrap.... my rowdy friend had pulled a couple of parts --probably the hold-down bar and catch-- off the trap to make it easier to conceal and more effective as a catapult... [leaving] the base, the spring, and the hammer. Not much of a mousetrap, but a helluva spitball launcher.... I realized why [Behe's] mousetrap analogy had bothered me. It was wrong. The mousetrap is not irreducibly complex after all.[৫১]

Other systems identified by Miller that include mousetrap components include the following:[৫১]

  • use the spitball launcher as a tie clip (same three-part system with different function)
  • remove the spring from the spitball launcher/tie clip to create a two-part key chain (base + hammer)
  • glue the spitball launcher/tie clip to a sheet of wood to create a clipboard (launcher + glue + wood)
  • remove the hold-down bar for use as a toothpick (single element system)

The point of the reduction is that - in biology - most or all of the components were already at hand, by the time it became necessary to build a mousetrap. As such, it required far fewer steps to develop a mousetrap than to design all the components from scratch.

Thus, the development of the mousetrap, said to consist of five different parts which had no function on their own, has been reduced to one step: the assembly from parts that are already present, performing other functions.

The Intelligent Design argument focuses on the functionality to catch mice. It skips over the case that many, if not all, parts are already available in their own right, at the time that the need for a mousetrap arises.

Consequences of irreducible complexity

Supporters of intelligent design argue that anything less than the complete form of such a system or organ would not work at all, or would in fact be a detriment to the organism, and would therefore never survive the process of natural selection. Although they accept that some complex systems and organs can be explained by evolution, they claim that organs and biological features which are irreducibly complex cannot be explained by current models, and that an intelligent designer must have created life or guided its evolution. Accordingly, the debate on irreducible complexity concerns two questions: whether irreducible complexity can be found in nature, and what significance it would have if it did exist in nature.[তথ্যসূত্র প্রয়োজন]

Behe's original examples of irreducibly complex mechanisms included the bacterial flagellum of E. coli, the blood clotting cascade, cilia, and the adaptive immune system.

Behe argues that organs and biological features which are irreducibly complex cannot be wholly explained by current models of evolution. In explicating his definition of "irreducible complexity" he notes that:

An irreducibly complex system cannot be produced directly (that is, by continuously improving the initial function, which continues to work by the same mechanism) by slight, successive modifications of a precursor system, because any precursor to an irreducibly complex system that is missing a part is by definition nonfunctional.

Irreducible complexity is not an argument that evolution does not occur, but rather an argument that it is "incomplete". In the last chapter of Darwin's Black Box, Behe goes on to explain his view that irreducible complexity is evidence for intelligent design. Mainstream critics, however, argue that irreducible complexity, as defined by Behe, can be generated by known evolutionary mechanisms. Behe's claim that no scientific literature adequately modeled the origins of biochemical systems through evolutionary mechanisms has been challenged by TalkOrigins.[৫২][৫৩] The judge in the Dover trial wrote "By defining irreducible complexity in the way that he has, Professor Behe attempts to exclude the phenomenon of exaptation by definitional fiat, ignoring as he does so abundant evidence which refutes his argument. Notably, the NAS has rejected Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity..."[৫৪]

Stated examples

Behe and others have suggested a number of biological features that they believe may be irreducibly complex.

Blood clotting cascade

The process of blood clotting or coagulation cascade in vertebrates is a complex biological pathway which is given as an example of apparent irreducible complexity.[৫৫]

The irreducible complexity argument assumes that the necessary parts of a system have always been necessary, and therefore could not have been added sequentially. However, in evolution, something which is at first merely advantageous can later become necessary.[৫৬] Natural selection can lead to complex biochemical systems being built up from simpler systems, or to existing functional systems being recombined as a new system with a different function.[৫৪] For example, one of the clotting factors that Behe listed as a part of the clotting cascade (Factor XII, also called Hageman factor) was later found to be absent in whales, demonstrating that it is not essential for a clotting system.[৫৭] Many purportedly irreducible structures can be found in other organisms as much simpler systems that utilize fewer parts. These systems, in turn, may have had even simpler precursors that are now extinct. Behe has responded to critics of his clotting cascade arguments by suggesting that homology is evidence for evolution, but not for natural selection.[৫৮]

The "improbability argument" also misrepresents natural selection. It is correct to say that a set of simultaneous mutations that form a complex protein structure is so unlikely as to be unfeasible, but that is not what Darwin advocated. His explanation is based on small accumulated changes that take place without a final goal. Each step must be advantageous in its own right, although biologists may not yet understand the reason behind all of them—for example, jawless fish accomplish blood clotting with just six proteins instead of the full ten.[৫৯]

Eye

Stages in the evolution of the eye
(a) A pigment spot
(b) A simple pigment cup
(c) The simple optic cup found in abalone
(d) The complex lensed eye of the marine snail and the octopus

The eye is an example of a supposedly irreducibly complex structure, due to its many elaborate and interlocking parts, seemingly all dependent upon one another. It is frequently cited by intelligent design and creationism advocates as an example of irreducible complexity. Behe used the "development of the eye problem" as evidence for intelligent design in Darwin's Black Box. Although Behe acknowledged that the evolution of the larger anatomical features of the eye have been well-explained, he pointed out that the complexity of the minute biochemical reactions required at a molecular level for light sensitivity still defies explanation. Creationist Jonathan Sarfati has described the eye as evolutionary biologists' "greatest challenge as an example of superb 'irreducible complexity' in God's creation", specifically pointing to the supposed "vast complexity" required for transparency.[৬০][যাচাইকরণ ব্যর্থ হয়েছে]

In an often misquoted[৬১] passage from On the Origin of Species, Charles Darwin appears to acknowledge the eye's development as a difficulty for his theory. However, the quote in context shows that Darwin actually had a very good understanding of the evolution of the eye (see fallacy of quoting out of context). He notes that "to suppose that the eye ... could have been formed by natural selection, seems, I freely confess, absurd in the highest possible degree". Yet this observation was merely a rhetorical device for Darwin. He goes on to explain that if gradual evolution of the eye could be shown to be possible, "the difficulty of believing that a perfect and complex eye could be formed by natural selection ... can hardly be considered real". He then proceeded to roughly map out a likely course for evolution using examples of gradually more complex eyes of various species.[৬২]

The eyes of vertebrates (left) and invertebrates such as the octopus (right) developed independently: vertebrates evolved an inverted retina with a blind spot over their optic disc, whereas octopuses avoided this with a non-inverted retina.

Since Darwin's day, the eye's ancestry has become much better understood. Although learning about the construction of ancient eyes through fossil evidence is problematic due to the soft tissues leaving no imprint or remains, genetic and comparative anatomical evidence has increasingly supported the idea of a common ancestry for all eyes.[৬৩][৬৪][৬৫]

Current evidence does suggest possible evolutionary lineages for the origins of the anatomical features of the eye. One likely chain of development is that the eyes originated as simple patches of photoreceptor cells that could detect the presence or absence of light, but not its direction. When, via random mutation across the population, the photosensitive cells happened to have developed on a small depression, it endowed the organism with a better sense of the light's source. This small change gave the organism an advantage over those without the mutation. This genetic trait would then be "selected for" as those with the trait would have an increased chance of survival, and therefore progeny, over those without the trait. Individuals with deeper depressions would be able to discern changes in light over a wider field than those individuals with shallower depressions. As ever deeper depressions were advantageous to the organism, gradually, this depression would become a pit into which light would strike certain cells depending on its angle. The organism slowly gained increasingly precise visual information. And again, this gradual process continued as individuals having a slightly shrunken aperture of the eye had an advantage over those without the mutation as an aperture increases how collimated the light is at any one specific group of photoreceptors. As this trait developed, the eye became effectively a pinhole camera which allowed the organism to dimly make out shapes—the nautilus is a modern example of an animal with such an eye. Finally, via this same selection process, a protective layer of transparent cells over the aperture was differentiated into a crude lens, and the interior of the eye was filled with humours to assist in focusing images.[৬৬][৬৭][৬৮] In this way, eyes are recognized by modern biologists as actually a relatively unambiguous and simple structure to evolve, and many of the major developments of the eye's evolution are believed to have taken place over only a few million years, during the Cambrian explosion.[৬৯] Behe asserts that this is only an explanation of the gross anatomical steps, however, and not an explanation of the changes in discrete biochemical systems that would have needed to take place.[৭০]

Behe maintains that the complexity of light sensitivity at the molecular level and the minute biochemical reactions required for those first "simple patches of photoreceptor[s]" still defies explanation, and that the proposed series of infinitesimal steps to get from patches of photoreceptors to a fully functional eye would actually be considered great, complex leaps in evolution if viewed on the molecular scale. Other intelligent design proponents claim that the evolution of the entire visual system would be difficult rather than the eye alone.[৭১]

Flagella

The flagella of certain bacteria constitute a molecular motor requiring the interaction of about 40 different protein parts. Behe presents this as a prime example of an irreducibly complex structure defined as "a single system composed of several well-matched, interacting parts that contribute to the basic function, wherein the removal of any one of the parts causes the system to effectively cease functioning", and argues that since "an irreducibly complex system that is missing a part is by definition nonfunctional", it could not have evolved gradually through natural selection.[৭২]

Reducible complexity. In contrast to Behe's claims, many proteins can be deleted or mutated and the flagellum still works, even though sometimes at reduced efficiency.[৭৩] In fact, the composition of flagella is surprisingly diverse across bacteria with many proteins only found in some species but not others.[৭৪] Hence the flagellar apparatus is clearly very flexible in evolutionary terms and perfectly able to lose or gain protein components. Further studies have shown that, contrary to claims of "irreducible complexity", flagella and related protein transport mechanisms show evidence of evolution through Darwinian processes, providing case studies in how complex systems can evolve from simpler components.[৭৫][৭৬] Multiple processes were involved in the evolution of the flagellum, including horizontal gene transfer.[৭৭]

Evolution from Type Three Secretion Systems. Scientists regard this argument as having been disproved in the light of research dating back to 1996 as well as more recent findings.[৭২][৭৮] They point out that the basal body of the flagella has been found to be similar to the Type III secretion system (TTSS), a needle-like structure that pathogenic germs such as Salmonella and Yersinia pestis use to inject toxins into living eucaryote cells. The needle's base has ten elements in common with the flagellum, but it is missing forty of the proteins that make a flagellum work.[৭৯] The TTSS system negates Behe's claim that taking away any one of the flagellum's parts would prevent the system from functioning. On this basis, Kenneth Miller notes that, "The parts of this supposedly irreducibly complex system actually have functions of their own."[৮০][৮১] Studies have also shown that similar parts of the flagellum in different bacterial species can have different functions despite showing evidence of common descent, and that certain parts of the flagellum can be removed without completely eliminating its functionality.[৮২]

Dembski has argued that phylogenetically, the TTSS is found in a narrow range of bacteria which makes it seem to him to be a late innovation, whereas flagella are widespread throughout many bacterial groups, and he argues that it was an early innovation.[৮৩][৮৪] Against Dembski's argument, different flagella use completely different mechanisms, and publications show a plausible path in which bacterial flagella could have evolved from a secretion system.[৮৫]

Biological wheels

The wheel is also stated as an irreducibly complex structure. Contrary to some other examples, its absence in nature has been said to provide evidence against intelligent design and creationism.[৮৬] Molecular biologist Robin Holliday has written that the absence of biological wheels argues against creationist or intelligent design accounts of the diversity of life, because an intelligent creator—free of the limitations imposed by evolution—would be expected to deploy wheels wherever they would be of use.[৮৭]

Response of the scientific community

Like intelligent design, the concept it seeks to support, irreducible complexity has failed to gain any notable acceptance within the scientific community. One science writer called it a "full-blown intellectual surrender strategy".[৮৮]

Reducibility of "irreducible" systems

Researchers have proposed potentially viable evolutionary pathways for allegedly irreducibly complex systems such as blood clotting, the immune system[৮৯] and the flagellum[৯০][৯১] - the three examples Behe proposed. John H. McDonald even showed his example of a mousetrap to be reducible.[৫০] If irreducible complexity is an insurmountable obstacle to evolution, it should not be possible to conceive of such pathways.[৯২]

Niall Shanks and Karl H. Joplin, both of East Tennessee State University, have shown that systems satisfying Behe's characterization of irreducible biochemical complexity can arise naturally and spontaneously as the result of self-organizing chemical processes.[৭] They also assert that what evolved biochemical and molecular systems actually exhibit is "redundant complexity"—a kind of complexity that is the product of an evolved biochemical process. They claim that Behe overestimated the significance of irreducible complexity because of his simple, linear view of biochemical reactions, resulting in his taking snapshots of selective features of biological systems, structures, and processes, while ignoring the redundant complexity of the context in which those features are naturally embedded. They also criticized his over-reliance of overly simplistic metaphors, such as his mousetrap.

A computer model of the co-evolution of proteins binding to DNA in the peer-reviewed journal Nucleic Acids Research consisted of several parts (DNA binders and DNA binding sites) which contribute to the basic function; removal of either one leads immediately to the death of the organism. This model fits the definition of irreducible complexity exactly, yet it evolves.[৯৩] (The program can be run from Ev program.)

In addition, research published in the peer-reviewed journal Nature has shown that computer simulations of evolution demonstrate that it is possible for complex features to evolve naturally.[৯৪]

One can compare a mousetrap with a cat in this context. Both normally function so as to control the mouse population. The cat has many parts that can be removed leaving it still functional; for example, its tail can be bobbed, or it can lose an ear in a fight. Comparing the cat and the mousetrap, then, one sees that the mousetrap (which is not alive) offers better evidence, in terms of irreducible complexity, for intelligent design than the cat. Even looking at the mousetrap analogy, several critics have described ways in which the parts of the mousetrap could have independent uses or could develop in stages, demonstrating that it is not irreducibly complex.[৫০][৫১]

Moreover, even cases where removing a certain component in an organic system will cause the system to fail do not demonstrate that the system could not have been formed in a step-by-step, evolutionary process. By analogy, stone arches are irreducibly complex—if you remove any stone the arch will collapse—yet humans build them easily enough, one stone at a time, by building over centering that is removed afterward. Similarly, naturally occurring arches of stone form by the weathering away of bits of stone from a large concretion that has formed previously.

Evolution can act to simplify as well as to complicate. This raises the possibility that seemingly irreducibly complex biological features may have been achieved with a period of increasing complexity, followed by a period of simplification.

A team led by Joseph Thornton, assistant professor of biology at the University of Oregon's Center for Ecology and Evolutionary Biology, using techniques for resurrecting ancient genes, reconstructed the evolution of an apparently irreducibly complex molecular system. The April 7, 2006 issue of Science published this research.[৬][৯৫]

Irreducible complexity may not actually exist in nature, and the examples given by Behe and others may not in fact represent irreducible complexity, but can be explained in terms of simpler precursors. The theory of facilitated variation challenges irreducible complexity. Marc W. Kirschner, a professor and chair of Department of Systems Biology at Harvard Medical School, and John C. Gerhart, a professor in Molecular and Cell Biology, University of California, Berkeley, presented this theory in 2005. They describe how certain mutation and changes can cause apparent irreducible complexity. Thus, seemingly irreducibly complex structures are merely "very complex", or they are simply misunderstood or misrepresented.

Gradual adaptation to new functions

The precursors of complex systems, when they are not useful in themselves, may be useful to perform other, unrelated functions. Evolutionary biologists argue that evolution often works in this kind of blind, haphazard manner in which the function of an early form is not necessarily the same as the function of the later form. The term used for this process is exaptation. The mammalian middle ear (derived from a jawbone) and the panda's thumb (derived from a wrist bone spur) provide classic examples. A 2006 article in Nature demonstrates intermediate states leading toward the development of the ear in a Devonian fish (about 360 million years ago).[৯৬] Furthermore, recent research shows that viruses play a heretofore unexpected role in evolution by mixing and matching genes from various hosts.[তথ্যসূত্র প্রয়োজন]

Arguments for irreducibility often assume that things started out the same way they ended up—as we see them now. However, that may not necessarily be the case. In the Dover trial an expert witness for the plaintiffs, Ken Miller, demonstrated this possibility using Behe's mousetrap analogy. By removing several parts, Miller made the object unusable as a mousetrap, but he pointed out that it was now a perfectly functional, if unstylish, tie clip.[৫১][৯৭]

Methods by which irreducible complexity may evolve

Irreducible complexity can be seen as equivalent to crossing a "valley" in a fitness landscape. A number of mathematical models of evolution have explored the circumstances under which this can happen.[৯৮][৯৯][১০০][১০১]

Falsifiability and experimental evidence

Some critics, such as Jerry Coyne (professor of evolutionary biology at the University of Chicago) and Eugenie Scott (a physical anthropologist and former executive director of the National Center for Science Education) have argued that the concept of irreducible complexity and, more generally, intelligent design is not falsifiable and, therefore, not scientific.

Behe argues that the theory that irreducibly complex systems could not have evolved can be falsified by an experiment where such systems are evolved. For example, he posits taking bacteria with no flagellum and imposing a selective pressure for mobility. If, after a few thousand generations, the bacteria evolved the bacterial flagellum, then Behe believes that this would refute his theory.[তথ্যসূত্র প্রয়োজন]

Other critics take a different approach, pointing to experimental evidence that they believe falsifies the argument for Intelligent Design from irreducible complexity. For example, Kenneth Miller cites the lab work of Barry G. Hall on E. coli, which he asserts is evidence that "Behe is wrong".[১০২]

Other evidence that irreducible complexity is not a problem for evolution comes from the field of computer science, which routinely uses computer analogues of the processes of evolution in order to automatically design complex solutions to problems. The results of such genetic algorithms are frequently irreducibly complex since the process, like evolution, both removes non-essential components over time as well as adding new components. The removal of unused components with no essential function, like the natural process where rock underneath a natural arch is removed, can produce irreducibly complex structures without requiring the intervention of a designer. Researchers applying these algorithms automatically produce human-competitive designs—but no human designer is required.[১০৩]

Argument from ignorance

Intelligent design proponents attribute to an intelligent designer those biological structures they believe are irreducibly complex and therefore they say a natural explanation is insufficient to account for them.[১০৪] However, critics view irreducible complexity as a special case of the "complexity indicates design" claim, and thus see it as an argument from ignorance and as a God-of-the-gaps argument.[১০৫]

Eugenie Scott, along with Glenn Branch and other critics, has argued that many points raised by intelligent-design proponents are arguments from ignorance.[১০৬] Behe has been accused by critics [১০৭][১০৮] of using an "argument by lack of imagination".

False dilemma

Irreducible complexity is at its core an argument against evolution. If truly irreducible systems are found, the argument goes, then intelligent design must be the correct explanation for their existence. However, this conclusion is based on the assumption that current evolutionary theory and intelligent design are the only two valid models to explain life, a false dilemma.[১০৯][১১০]

Irreducible complexity in the Dover trial

While testifying during the 2005 Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District trial, Behe conceded that there are no peer-reviewed papers supporting his claims that complex molecular systems, like the bacterial flagellum, the blood-clotting cascade, and the immune system, were intelligently designed nor are there any peer-reviewed articles supporting his argument that certain complex molecular structures are "irreducibly complex."[১১১]

In the final ruling of Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District, Judge Jones specifically singled out Behe and irreducible complexity:[১১১]

  • "Professor Behe admitted in "Reply to My Critics" that there was a defect in his view of irreducible complexity because, while it purports to be a challenge to natural selection, it does not actually address "the task facing natural selection." and that "Professor Behe wrote that he hoped to "repair this defect in future work..." (Page 73)
  • "As expert testimony revealed, the qualification on what is meant by "irreducible complexity" renders it meaningless as a criticism of evolution. (3:40 (Miller)). In fact, the theory of evolution proffers exaptation as a well-recognized, well-documented explanation for how systems with multiple parts could have evolved through natural means." (Page 74)
  • "By defining irreducible complexity in the way that he has, Professor Behe attempts to exclude the phenomenon of exaptation by definitional fiat, ignoring as he does so abundant evidence which refutes his argument. Notably, the NAS has rejected Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity..." (Page 75)
  • "As irreducible complexity is only a negative argument against evolution, it is refutable and accordingly testable, unlike ID [Intelligent Design], by showing that there are intermediate structures with selectable functions that could have evolved into the allegedly irreducibly complex systems. (2:15-16 (Miller)). Importantly, however, the fact that the negative argument of irreducible complexity is testable does not make testable the argument for ID. (2:15 (Miller); 5:39 (Pennock)). Professor Behe has applied the concept of irreducible complexity to only a few select systems: (1) the bacterial flagellum; (2) the blood-clotting cascade; and (3) the immune system. Contrary to Professor Behe's assertions with respect to these few biochemical systems among the myriad existing in nature, however, Dr. Miller presented evidence, based upon peer-reviewed studies, that they are not in fact irreducibly complex." (Page 76)
  • "...on cross-examination, Professor Behe was questioned concerning his 1996 claim that science would never find an evolutionary explanation for the immune system. He was presented with fifty-eight peer-reviewed publications, nine books, and several immunology textbook chapters about the evolution of the immune system; however, he simply insisted that this was still not sufficient evidence of evolution, and that it was not "good enough." (23:19 (Behe))." (Page 78)
  • "We therefore find that Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity has been refuted in peer-reviewed research papers and has been rejected by the scientific community at large. (17:45-46 (Padian); 3:99 (Miller)). Additionally, even if irreducible complexity had not been rejected, it still does not support ID as it is merely a test for evolution, not design. (2:15, 2:35-40 (Miller); 28:63-66 (Fuller)). We will now consider the purportedly "positive argument" for design encompassed in the phrase used numerous times by Professors Behe and Minnich throughout their expert testimony, which is the "purposeful arrangement of parts." Professor Behe summarized the argument as follows: We infer design when we see parts that appear to be arranged for a purpose. The strength of the inference is quantitative; the more parts that are arranged, the more intricately they interact, the stronger is our confidence in design. The appearance of design in aspects of biology is overwhelming. Since nothing other than an intelligent cause has been demonstrated to be able to yield such a strong appearance of design, Darwinian claims notwithstanding, the conclusion that the design seen in life is real design is rationally justified. (18:90-91, 18:109-10 (Behe); 37:50 (Minnich)). As previously indicated, this argument is merely a restatement of the Reverend William Paley's argument applied at the cell level. Minnich, Behe, and Paley reach the same conclusion, that complex organisms must have been designed using the same reasoning, except that Professors Behe and Minnich refuse to identify the designer, whereas Paley inferred from the presence of design that it was God. (1:6- 7 (Miller); 38:44, 57 (Minnich)). Expert testimony revealed that this inductive argument is not scientific and as admitted by Professor Behe, can never be ruled out. (2:40 (Miller); 22:101 (Behe); 3:99 (Miller))." (Pages 79–80)

Notes and references

  1. "We therefore find that Professor Behe's claim for irreducible complexity has been refuted in peer-reviewed research papers and has been rejected by the scientific community at large." Ruling, Judge John E. Jones III, Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District
  2. "True in this latest creationist variant, advocates of so-called intelligent design ... use more slick, pseudoscientific language. They talk about things like "irreducible complexity" Shulman, Seth (২০০৬)। Undermining science: suppression and distortion in the Bush Administration। Berkeley: University of California Press। পৃষ্ঠা 13। আইএসবিএন 0-520-24702-7  "for most members of the mainstream scientific community, ID is not a scientific theory, but a creationist pseudoscience."
    David Mu (Fall ২০০৫)। "Trojan Horse or Legitimate Science: Deconstructing the Debate over Intelligent Design" (পিডিএফ)Harvard Science Review19 (1)। ২০০৭-০৭-২৪ তারিখে মূল (পিডিএফ) থেকে আর্কাইভ করা। 
    Perakh M (Summer ২০০৫)। "Why Intelligent Design Isn't Intelligent — Review of: Unintelligent Design"Cell Biol Educ.4 (2): 121–2। ডিওআই:10.1187/cbe.05-02-0071পিএমসি 1103713অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
    Mark D. Decker. College of Biological Sciences, General Biology Program, University of Minnesota Frequently Asked Questions About the Texas Science Textbook Adoption Controversy "The Discovery Institute and ID proponents have a number of goals that they hope to achieve using disingenuous and mendacious methods of marketing, publicity, and political persuasion. They do not practice real science because that takes too long, but mainly because this method requires that one have actual evidence and logical reasons for one's conclusions, and the ID proponents just don't have those. If they had such resources, they would use them, and not the disreputable methods they actually use."
    See also list of scientific societies explicitly rejecting intelligent design
  3. Ker Than (সেপ্টেম্বর ২৩, ২০০৫)। "Why scientists dismiss 'intelligent design' - LiveScience"msnbc.com। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০১০-০৫-১৭ 
  4. Scott EC, Matzke NJ (মে ২০০৭)। "Biological design in science classrooms"Proc Natl Acad Sci USA104 (suppl_1): 8669–76, See page 8672। ডিওআই:10.1073/pnas.0701505104পিএমআইডি 17494747পিএমসি 1876445অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্যবিবকোড:2007PNAS..104.8669S 
  5. *Behe, Michael (১৯৯৬)। Darwin's Black Box। New York: Free Press। আইএসবিএন 978-0-684-82754-4 
  6. Bridgham JT, Carroll SM, Thornton JW (এপ্রিল ২০০৬)। "Evolution of hormone-receptor complexity by molecular exploitation"। Science312 (5770): 97–101। ডিওআই:10.1126/science.1123348পিএমআইডি 16601189বিবকোড:2006Sci...312...97B 
  7. Shanks, Niall; Joplin, Karl H. (১৯৯৯)। "Redundant Complexity: A Critical Analysis of Intelligent Design in Biochemistry"। Philosophy of Science। The University of Chicago Press। 66 (2, June): 268–282। জেস্টোর 188646ডিওআই:10.1086/392687 
  8. http://www.nature.com/nature/journal/v481/n7381/full/nature10724.html
  9. http://www.biomedcentral.com/1471-2148/10/341
  10. Darwin's Black Box page 39 in the 2006 edition
  11. In Defense of the Irreducibility of the Blood Clotting Cascade: Response to Russell Doolittle, Ken Miller and Keith Robison, July 31, 2000, Discovery Institute article
  12. No Free Lunch: Why Specified Complexity Cannot Be Purchased without Intelligence. by William Dembski pp. 285
  13. William Paley:Natural Theology; or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity. Collected from the Appearances of Nature 12th edition, 1809
  14. On the Nature of the Gods, translated by Francis Brooks, London: Methuen, 1896.
  15. See Henry Hallam Introduction to the Literature of Europe in the Fifteenth, Sixteenth, and Seventeenth Centuries Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1854 volume 2 page 385 part iii chapter iii section i paragraph 26 footnote u
  16. De Formatione Foetus=The Construction of the Embryo, chapter 11 in Galen: Selected Works, translated by P. N. Singer, The World's Classics, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1997 আইএসবিএন ৯৭৮-০-১৯-২৮২৪৫০-৯. One 18th-century reference to Galen is David Hume Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, 1779, Part 12, § 3, page 215. Also see Galen's De Usu Partium=On the Usefulness of the Parts of the Body, translated and edited by Margaret Tallmadge May, Ithaca, New York, Cornell University Press, 1968, especially book XVII. For a relevant discussion of Galen and other ancients see pages 121-122, Goodman, Lenn Evan (২০১০)। Creation and evolution। Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon and New York: Routledge। আইএসবিএন 978-0-415-91380-5 
  17. De Generatione Animalium, chapter III. Partial translation in: Howard B. Adelmann, Marcello Malpighi and the Evolution of Embryology Ithaca, New York, Cornell University Press, 1966, volume 2, pages 811-812.
  18. John Wilkins,Of the Principles and Duties of Natural Religion, London, 1675, book I, chapter 6, page 82.
  19. The Sacred Theory of the Earth, 2nd edition, London: Walter Kettilby, 1691. Book I Chapter IV page 43
  20. Nicolas Malebranche (১৭১২)। De la recherche de la verité: où l'on traite de la nature de l'esprit de l'homme, & de l'usage qu'il en doit faire pour éviter l'erreur dans les sciences (6ième সংস্করণ)। Paris: Chez Michel David।  Livre 6ième, 2ième partie, chapître 4; English translation: Nicholas Malebranche (১৯৯৭)। Thomas M. Lennon; Paul J. Olscamp, সম্পাদকগণ। The Search After Truth: With Elucidations of The Search After Truth। Cambridge: Cambridge University Press। আইএসবিএন 0-521-58004-8  Second paragraph from the end of the chapter, on page 465.
  21. Pages 202-204 of Andrew Pyle (২০০৬)। "Malebranche on Animal Generation: Preexistence and the Microscope"। Smith JH। The problem of animal generation in early modern philosophy। Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press। পৃষ্ঠা 194–214। আইএসবিএন 0-521-84077-5 
  22. The Chicken or the Egg
  23. This is Guyer's exposition on page 22 of Paul Guyer (১৯৯২)। "Introduction"। Paul Guyer। The Cambridge Companion to Kant। Cambridge: Cambridge University Press। পৃষ্ঠা 1–25। আইএসবিএন 978-0-521-36768-4  Guyer adds this parenthetical comment: "(here is where the theory of natural selection removes the difficulty)". See Kant's discussion in section IX of the "First Introduction" to the Critique of Judgment and in §§61, 64 (where he uses the expression wechselsweise abhängt="reciprocally dependent"), and §66 of "Part Two, First Division". For example, Immanuel Kant (২০০০)। "§64"। Paul Guyer; Eric Matthews। Critique of the power of judgment। Cambridge: Cambridge University Press। পৃষ্ঠা 243–244। আইএসবিএন 0-521-34447-6  German original Kritik der Urtheilskraft। Kants gesammelte Schriften। 5 (Königlich Preußischen Akademie der Wißenschaften সংস্করণ)। Berlin: Georg Reimer। ১৯১৩। পৃষ্ঠা 371। আইএসবিএন 978-3-11-001438-9 
  24. See especially chapters VI and VII of William Coleman (১৯৬৪)। Georges Cuvier, Zoologist: A Study in the History of Evolution Theory। Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press।  See also the discussion of these principles in the Wikipedia article on Cuvier.
  25. Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray. page 189, Chapter VI
  26. See for example, Alan R. Rogers (২০১১)। The Evidence for Evolution। Chicago: University of Chicago Press। আইএসবিএন 978-0-226-72382-2  in pages 37–38, 48–49 citing Joseph John Murphy accepting natural selection within limits, excepting "the eye" with its multiple parts. Joseph John Murphy (নভেম্বর ১৯, ১৮৬৬)। "Presidential Address to the Belfast Natural History and Philosophical Society"Northern Whig। Belfast।  and in page 48 citing C. Pritchard। "Appendix Note A On the Origin of Species by Natural Selection"। The Continuity of the Schemes of Nature and Revelation: A Sermon Preached, by request, on the occasion of the meeting of the British Association at Nottingham. With remarks on some relations of modern knowledge to theology। London: Bell and Daldy। পৃষ্ঠা 31–37। , especially page 33
  27. Page 594 in: Herbert Spencer (অক্টোবর ১৮৯৪)। "Weismannism Once More"। The Contemporary Review66: 592–608।  Another essay of Spencer's treating this concept is: Herbert Spencer (১৮৯৩)। "The Inadequacy of "Natural Selection""। The Contemporary Review63: 153–166।  (Part I: February) and pages 439-456 (Part II: March). These essays were reprinted in Herbert Spencer (১৮৯১)। The Works of Herbert Spencer17। London: Williams and Norgate।  (also Osnabrück: Otto Zeller, 1967). See also part III, Chapter XII, §166, pages 449-457 in: Herbert Spencer (১৮৬৪)। Principles of BiologyI। London: Williams and Norgate।  And: Herbert Spencer (১৮৮৬)। "The Factors of Organic Evolution"। The Nineteenth Century19: 570–589।  (Part I: April) and pages 749-770 (Part II: May). "Factors" was reprinted in pages 389-466 of Herbert Spencer (১৮৯১)। The Works of Herbert Spencer13। London: Williams and Norgate।  (also Osnabrück: Otto Zeller, 1967)= volume 1 of Essays: Scientific, Political, and Speculative.
  28. One example of a response was in Section III(γ) pages 32-42 of August Weismann (১৯০৯)। "The Selection theory"। Albert Charles SewardDarwin and Modern Science: Essays in Commemoration of the Centenary of the Birth of Charles Darwin and of the Fiftieth Anniversary of the Publication of The Origin of Species। Cambridge: Cambridge University Press। পৃষ্ঠা 19–65।  See also Chapter VII, §12(1), pages 237-238 in: J. Arthur Thomson (১৯০৮)। Heredity। London: John Murray।  Both of these referred to what has become known as the Baldwin effect. An analysis of both sides of the issue is: George John Romanes (১৮৯৫)। "III: Characters as Hereditary and Acquired (continued)"। Darwin and After Darwin: Post-Darwinian Questions, Heredity, UtilityII। London: Longman, Green। পৃষ্ঠা 60–102। 
  29. Charles Darwin (১৮৬৮)। "XXV. Laws of Variation continued - Correlated Variability"। The Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication2। London: John Murray। পৃষ্ঠা 321–338।  especially page 333 and following.
  30. Pages 67-68 in: Mark Ridley (মার্চ ১৯৮২)। "Coadapatation and the Inadequacy of Natural Selection"। British Journal for the History of Science15 (1): 45–68। ডিওআই:10.1017/S0007087400018938 
  31. St. George Jackson Mivart (১৮৭১)। On the Genesis of Species। London: Macmillan। পৃষ্ঠা 52। 
  32. Asher, Robert J. (২০১২)। Evolution and belief: confessions of a religious paleontologist। Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press। পৃষ্ঠা 214। আইএসবিএন 9780521193832  See also Irreducible Complexity and the references cited there.
  33. Muller HJ (১৯১৮)। "Genetic variability, twin hybrids and constant hybrids, in a case of balanced lethal factors"Genetics3 (5): 422–99। পিএমআইডি 17245914পিএমসি 1200446অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য , especially pages 463–4.
  34. Muller HJ (১৯৩৯)। "Reversibility in evolution considered from the standpoint of genetics"। Biological Reviews of the Cambridge Philosophical Society4 (3): 261–80, quotation from 272। 
  35. Morris, Henry (১৯৭৪)। Scientific creationism (2nd সংস্করণ)। San Diego, Calif: Creation-Life Publishers। পৃষ্ঠা 59। আইএসবিএন 0-89051-003-2 
  36. T. H. Frazzetta, Complex Adaptations in Evolving Populations, Sunderland, Massachusetts: Sinauer Associates, 1975. আইএসবিএন ০-৮৭৮৯৩-১৯৪-৫. Referencing pages 3, 4-7, 7-20, and xi, respectively.
  37. Keough, Mark J.; Geisler, Norman L. (১৯৮২)। The Creator in the courtroom "Scopes II": the 1981 Arkansas creation-evolution trial। Milford, Mich: Mott Media। পৃষ্ঠা 146। আইএসবিএন 0-88062-020-X 
  38. Cairns-Smith, A. G. (১৯৮৫)। Seven clues to the origin of life: a scientific detective story। Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press। পৃষ্ঠা 39, 58–64। আইএসবিএন 0-521-27522-9 
  39. McShea, Daniel W. and Wim Hordijk. "Complexity by Subtraction." Evolutionary Biology (April 2013). PDF.
  40. Mark Perakh (২০০৮)। "Bacteria Flagella Look Like Man-made Machines"14 (3)। Skeptic (U.S. magazine)। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০০৮-১২-০৬ 
  41. Lumsden RD (জুন ১৯৯৪)। "Not So Blind A Watchmaker"। Creation Research Society Quarterly31 (1): 13–22, quotations from 13, 20। 
  42. Ludwig von Bertalanffy (1952). Problems of Life: An Evaluation of Modern Biological and Scientific Thought, pg 148 আইএসবিএন ১-১৩১-৭৯২৪২-৪
  43. Monod, Jacques (১৯৭২)। Chance and necessity: an essay on the natural philosophy of modern biology। New York: Vintage Books। আইএসবিএন 0-394-71825-9 
  44. Barbara Forrest, The Wedge at Work ওয়েব্যাক মেশিনে আর্কাইভকৃত ২০১৪-০৯-০৫ তারিখে. Talk Reason.
    Forrest B (২০০১)। "1: The Wedge at Work: How Intelligent Design Creationism is Wedging its way into the Cultural and Academic Mainstream"। Pennock RT। Intelligent design creationism and its critics: philosophical, theological, and scientific perspectives। Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press। পৃষ্ঠা 5–54। আইএসবিএন 0-262-66124-1 
  45. The New Pandas: Has Creationist Scholarship Improved? Comments on 1993 Revisions by Frank J. Sonleitner (1994)
    Introduction: Of Pandas and People, the foundational work of the 'Intelligent Design' movement by Nick Matzke 2004,
    Design on Trial in Dover, Pennsylvania by Nicholas J Matzke, NCSE Public Information Project Specialist
  46. Behe MJ (নভেম্বর ২০০১)। "Reply to My Critics: A Response to Reviews of Darwin's Black Box: The Biochemical Challenge to Evolution" (পিডিএফ)Biology and Philosophy16 (5): 685–709। ডিওআই:10.1023/A:1012268700496 
  47. Behe's testimony in Kitzmiller v. Dover
  48. Behe, Michael 2005 Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District 4: whether ID is science (p. 88)
  49. Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District 6: Conclusion, section H
  50. A reducibly complex mousetrap (graphics-intensive, requires JavaScript)
  51. Miller, Kenneth R. (২০০৮)। Only A Theory। New York: Viking Penguin। পৃষ্ঠা 54–55। আইএসবিএন 978-0-670-01883-3 
  52. Claim CA350: Professional literature is silent on the subject of the evolution of biochemical systems TalkOrigins Archive.
  53. Behe, Michael J. (১৯৯৬) [1996]। Darwin's black box: the biochemical challenge to evolution। New York, NY: Free Press। পৃষ্ঠা 72। আইএসবিএন 0-684-82754-9Yet here again the evolutionary literature is totally missing. No scientist has ever published a model to account for the gradual evolution of this extraordinary molecular machine. 
  54. Ruling, Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District, December 2005. Page 74.
  55. Action, George "Behe and the Blood Clotting Cascade"
  56. Boudry, Maarten; Blancke, Stefaan; Braeckman, Johan (সেপ্টেম্বর ২০১০)। "Irreducible Incoherence and Intelligent Design: A Look into the Conceptual Toolbox of a Pseudoscience"Quarterly Review of Biology85 (3): 473–82। ডিওআই:10.1086/656904পিএমআইডি 21243965 
  57. Semba U, Shibuya Y, Okabe H, Yamamoto T (১৯৯৮)। "Whale Hageman factor (factor XII): prevented production due to pseudogene conversion"। Thromb Res90 (1): 31–7। ডিওআই:10.1016/S0049-3848(97)00307-1পিএমআইডি 9678675 
  58. Behe, Michael "In Defense of the Irreducibility of the Blood Clotting Cascade: Response to Russell Doolittle, Ken Miller and Keith Robison"
  59. Creationism special: A sceptic's guide to intelligent design, New Scientist, 9 July 2005
  60. Sarfati, Jonathan (2000). Argument: 'Irreducible complexity', from Refuting Evolution (Answers in Genesis).
  61. CA113.1: Evolution of the eye
  62. Darwin, Charles (1859). On the Origin of Species. London: John Murray. pages 186ff, Chapter VI
  63. Halder G, Callaerts P, Gehring WJ (অক্টোবর ১৯৯৫)। "New perspectives on eye evolution"Current Opinion in Genetics & Development5 (5): 602–9। ডিওআই:10.1016/0959-437X(95)80029-8পিএমআইডি 8664548 
  64. Halder G, Callaerts P, Gehring WJ (মার্চ ১৯৯৫)। "Induction of ectopic eyes by targeted expression of the eyeless gene in Drosophila"Science267 (5205): 1788–92। ডিওআই:10.1126/science.7892602পিএমআইডি 7892602বিবকোড:1995Sci...267.1788H 
  65. Tomarev SI, Callaerts P, Kos L, ও অন্যান্য (মার্চ ১৯৯৭)। "Squid Pax-6 and eye development"Proc Natl Acad Sci USA94 (6): 2421–6। ডিওআই:10.1073/pnas.94.6.2421পিএমআইডি 9122210পিএমসি 20103অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্যবিবকোড:1997PNAS...94.2421T 
  66. Fernald, Russell D. (2001). The Evolution of Eyes: Why Do We See What We See? Karger Gazette 64: "The Eye in Focus".
  67. Fernald RD (১৯৮৮)। "Aquatic Adaptations in Fish Eyes"। Atema J। Sensory biology of aquatic animals। Berlin: Springer-Verlag। আইএসবিএন 0-387-96373-1 
  68. Fernald RD (১৯৯৭)। "The evolution of eyes"। Brain Behav Evol.50 (4): 253–9। ডিওআই:10.1159/000113339পিএমআইডি 9310200 
  69. Conway-Morris S (১৯৯৯)। The Crucible of Creation: The Burgess Shale and the Rise of Animals। Oxford [Oxfordshire]: Oxford University Press। আইএসবিএন 0-19-286202-2 
  70. Behe, Michael (২০০৬)। Darwin's Black Box। Free Press। পৃষ্ঠা 38। আইএসবিএন 978-0-7432-9031-9 
  71. Benjamin Wiker; Jonathan Witt (২০০৬)। A Meaningful World। পৃষ্ঠা 44। 
  72. Miller, Kenneth R. The Flagellum Unspun: The Collapse of "Irreducible Complexity" with reply here [১]
  73. Rajagopala SV, Titz B, Goll J, Parrish JR, Wohlbold K, McKevitt MT, Palzkill T, Mori H, Finley RL Jr, Uetz P (২০০৭)। "The protein network of bacterial motility"Mol Syst Biol.3: 128। ডিওআই:10.1038/msb4100166পিএমআইডি 17667950পিএমসি 1943423অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  74. Titz B, Rajagopala SV, Ester C, Häuser R, Uetz P (নভে ২০০৬)। "Novel conserved assembly factor of the bacterial flagellum"J Bacteriol188 (21): 7700–6। ডিওআই:10.1128/JB.00820-06পিএমআইডি 16936039পিএমসি 1636259অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  75. Pallen, M. J.; Gophna, U. (২০০৭)। "Bacterial Flagella and Type III Secretion: Case Studies in the Evolution of Complexity"। Gene and Protein Evolution। Genome Dynamics। 3: 30–47। আইএসবিএন 3-8055-8340-0ডিওআই:10.1159/000107602 
  76. Clements, A.; Bursac, D.; Gatsos, X.; Perry, A.; Civciristov, S.; Celik, N.; Likic, V.; Poggio, S.; Jacobs-Wagner, C.; Strugnell, R. A.; Lithgow, T. (২০০৯)। "The reducible complexity of a mitochondrial molecular machine"Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America106 (37): 15791–15795। ডিওআই:10.1073/pnas.0908264106পিএমআইডি 19717453পিএমসি 2747197অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্যবিবকোড:2009PNAS..10615791C 
  77. Zuckerkandl, Emile (ডিসেম্বর ২০০৬)। "Intelligent design and biological complexity"। Gene385: 2–18। ডিওআই:10.1016/j.gene.2006.03.025পিএমআইডি 17011142 
  78. Pallen, M.J.; Matzke, N.J. (২০০৬)। "From The Origin of Species to the origin of bacterial flagella"। Nature Reviews Microbiology4 (10): 784–790। ডিওআই:10.1038/nrmicro1493পিএমআইডি 16953248 
  79. Kenneth Miller's The Collapse of Intelligent Design: Section 5 Bacterial Flagellum (Case Western Reserve University, 2006 January 3)
  80. Unlocking cell secrets bolsters evolutionists (Chicago Tribune, 2006 February 13)
  81. Evolution in (Brownian) space: a model for the origin of the bacterial flagellum (Talk Design, 2006 September)
  82. Egelman, E. H. (১ জানুয়ারি ২০১৩)। "Intelligent Design A2 - Maloy, Stanley"Brenner's Encyclopedia of Genetics (Second Edition)। Academic Press: 112–114। ডিওআই:10.1016/B978-0-12-374984-0.00806-8 
  83. Spinning Tales About the Bacterial Flagellum
  84. Dembski, Rebuttal to Reports by Opposing Expert Witnesses, p. 52
  85. Isaak, Mark (২০০৬)। "CB200.1: Bacterial flagella and Irreducibly Complexity"। TalkOrigins Archive। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২৫ জুন ২০১৩ 
  86. Why Don't Any Animals Have Wheels?
  87. Holliday, Robin (জুন ২০০৩)। "Creationism and the wheel"। BioEssays। Wiley Periodicals। 25 (6): 620–621। আইএসএসএন 1521-1878ডিওআই:10.1002/bies.10280পিএমআইডি 12766952 
  88. Mirsky, Steve Sticker Shock: In the beginning was the cautionary advisory Scientific American, February 2005
  89. Matt Inlay, 2002. "Evolving Immunity." In TalkDesign.org.
  90. Nicholas J. Matzke, 2003. "Evolution in (Brownian) space: a model for the origin of the bacterial flagellum."
  91. Pallen MJ, Matzke NJ (অক্টোবর ২০০৬)। "From The Origin of Species to the origin of bacterial flagella"Nature Reviews Microbiology4 (10): 784–90। ডিওআই:10.1038/nrmicro1493পিএমআইডি 16953248 
  92. Pigliucci, Massimo [২] Collaboration Sept. 2001
  93. Schneider TD (২০০০)। "Evolution of Biological Information"Nucleic Acids Research28 (14): 2794–2799। ডিওআই:10.1093/nar/28.14.2794পিএমআইডি 10908337পিএমসি 102656অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  94. Lenski RE, Ofria C, Pennock RT, Adami C (২০০৩)। "The evolutionary origin of complex features"। Nature423 (6936): 139–44। ডিওআই:10.1038/nature01568পিএমআইডি 12736677বিবকোড:2003Natur.423..139L 
  95. Press release University of Oregon, April 4, 2006.
  96. M. Brazeau; P. Ahlberg (জানুয়ারি ১৯, ২০০৬)। "Tetrapod-like middle ear architecture in a Devonian fish"। Nature439 (7074): 318–21। ডিওআই:10.1038/nature04196পিএমআইডি 16421569বিবকোড:2006Natur.439..318B 
  97. "NOVA: Transcripts: Judgment Day: Intelligent Design on Trial Chapter 8"PBS। নভেম্বর ১৩, ২০০৭। সংগ্রহের তারিখ ২০০৮-১২-১৭ 
  98. Weissman, Daniel B.; Desai, Michael M.; Fisher, Daniel S.; Feldman, Marcus W. (জুন ২০০৯)। "The rate at which asexual populations cross fitness valleys"। Theoretical Population Biology75 (4): 286–300। ডিওআই:10.1016/j.tpb.2009.02.006 
  99. Weissman, D. B.; Feldman, M. W.; Fisher, D. S. (৫ অক্টোবর ২০১০)। "The Rate of Fitness-Valley Crossing in Sexual Populations"Genetics186 (4): 1389–1410। ডিওআই:10.1534/genetics.110.123240পিএমআইডি 20923976পিএমসি 2998319অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  100. Trotter, Meredith V.; Weissman, Daniel B.; Peterson, Grant I.; Peck, Kayla M.; Masel, Joanna (ডিসেম্বর ২০১৪)। "Cryptic genetic variation can make "irreducible complexity" a common mode of adaptation in sexual populations"Evolution68 (12): 3357–3367। ডিওআই:10.1111/evo.12517পিএমআইডি 25178652পিএমসি 4258170অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  101. Covert, Arthur; Lenski, Richard; Wilke, Claus; Ofria, Charles (২০১৩)। "Experiments on the role of deleterious mutations as stepping stones in adaptive evolution"Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences110 (34): E3171–E3178। ডিওআই:10.1073/pnas.1313424110পিএমআইডি 23918358পিএমসি 3752215অবাধে প্রবেশযোগ্য 
  102. Miller K (১৯৯৯)। Finding Darwin's God: a scientist's search for common ground between God and evolution। New York: Cliff Street Books। আইএসবিএন 0-06-093049-7 
  103. 36 Human-Competitive Results Produced by Genetic Programming
  104. Michael Behe. Evidence for Intelligent Design from Biochemistry. 1996.
  105. Index to Creationist Claims. Mark Isaak. The Talk.Origins Archive. "Irreducible complexity and complex specified information are special cases of the "complexity indicates design" claim; they are also arguments from incredulity." [৩] "The argument from incredulity creates a god of the gaps." [৪]
  106. Eugenie C. Scott and Glenn Branch, "Intelligent Design" Not Accepted by Most Scientists, National Center for Science Education website, September 10, 2002.
  107. Patheos.com essay: An argument premised on the author's lack of imagination.[৫]
  108. Amerikanbeat.net: A Critique of Behe, Dembski on "Irreducible Complexity"[৬]
  109. IC and Evolution makes the point that: if "irreducible complexity" is tautologically redefined to allow a valid argument that intelligent design is the correct explanation for life then there is no such thing as "irreducible complexity" in the mechanisms of life; while, if we use the unmodified original definition then "irreducible complexity" has nothing whatever to do with evolution.
  110. The Court in Dover noted that this implicit assumption of the defendant school board created a "flawed and illogical contrived dualism" (Opinion p. 64).
  111. Memorandum Opinion, Judge John E. Jones III, Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District

Additional references

External links

Supportive
Critical


সতর্কীকরণ: পূর্বনির্ধারিত সাজানোর চাবি "Irreducible Complexity" পূর্বের পূর্বনির্ধারিত সাজানোর চাবি "Homosexuality And Psychology" কে অগ্রাহ্য করে।